agmben dead

Upload: bustakay

Post on 02-Jun-2018

215 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/11/2019 Agmben Dead

    1/22

    Giorgio Agamben and the Politics of the Living Dead

    Author(s): Andrew NorrisSource: Diacritics, Vol. 30, No. 4 (Winter, 2000), pp. 38-58Published by: The Johns Hopkins University PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1566307.

    Accessed: 17/06/2014 02:46

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    The Johns Hopkins University Pressis collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to

    Diacritics.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 192.43.227.18 on Tue, 17 Jun 2014 02:46:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=jhuphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/1566307?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/1566307?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=jhup
  • 8/11/2019 Agmben Dead

    2/22

    IOR IO

    G MBEN

    N D

    T H E

    POLITICS

    O

    T H E

    LIVIN

    D E D

    ANDREWNORRIS

    Death is most

    rightening,

    since it is a

    boundary.

    -Aristotle,

    NicomacheanEthics

    And as the same

    thing

    there exists in us

    living

    and dead and

    the

    waking

    and

    the

    sleeping

    and

    young

    and old:

    for

    these

    things having changed

    round

    are

    those,

    and

    those

    having

    changed

    round

    are these.

    -Heraclitus,

    Fragment

    88

    What

    s

    politics today?

    What is its

    relationship

    o

    the

    tradition rom which

    it

    emerges?

    Thequestionsare difficult ones to answer n partbecausecontemporary olitics seems

    so

    schizophrenic.

    n

    affluentWestern ountries

    politics

    is

    increasingly

    a matterof

    spec-

    tacle

    on the one handand

    managed

    economies

    on the

    other.Hannah

    Arendtseems

    quite

    confirmed

    n her

    claim that

    the

    once-glorious

    public

    realm of

    appearance

    s fundamen-

    tally

    degraded

    when

    it is

    overrun

    by

    concerns more

    appropriate

    o the

    private

    realm,

    such as household

    management

    and

    gossip.

    If

    this "unnatural

    rowth

    of the

    natural"

    [47]

    inclines us to

    nostalgia

    for a time

    when

    the two realms were more

    decisively

    sepa-

    rated,

    such

    nostalgia

    is

    likely

    intensified

    by

    the "ethnic

    cleansing," rape camps,

    and

    genocide

    that we now associate with names such

    as

    "Yugoslavia"

    nd

    "Rwanda."

    But

    as

    improbable

    as

    any flight

    to the

    pastmaybe,

    it is even less

    likely

    that

    the

    politics

    of

    that

    past

    could

    help

    us

    navigate

    the

    treacherouswaters

    of our

    current

    technological

    society.

    I

    have

    in

    mind

    not

    only

    the familiar

    claim

    that

    the

    attempted

    genocides

    of our

    time

    are

    only

    made

    possible

    by quite

    modem

    forms

    of

    technology, organization,

    and

    experience,'

    but also

    recent scientific

    and

    "medical"advances.Consider

    ust

    two:

    first,

    the

    corporate

    driven and controlled

    development

    of

    biotechnologies,

    in

    which

    huge

    multinationals

    re

    acquiringpatents

    o

    genetic

    "information"uch as "all

    humanblood

    cells that have come

    from the

    umbilical

    cord of

    [any]

    newborn

    child."

    If

    there

    is

    any

    doubt that such

    developments

    will lead us

    to

    redefine

    the human

    being,

    these

    may

    be

    laid

    to rest

    by

    the case

    of

    John

    Moore,

    an

    Alaskan

    businessmanwho found

    his own

    body partshadbeenpatented,withouthis knowledge, by theUniversityof Californiaat

    Los

    Angeles

    and icensed to

    the

    Sandoz

    Pharmaceutical

    Corporation

    Rifkin

    60-61].

    So

    much for Locke's

    attempt

    o

    ground

    the institutionof

    privateproperty

    n the fact

    that

    "every

    Man has

    a

    Property

    n his own Person" 2 In its

    place

    we

    seem

    to be

    moving

    I

    am

    grateful

    to

    GiorgioAgamben,

    Joe

    Campisi,

    Bill

    Connolly,

    Tom

    Rockmore,

    Hans

    Sluga,

    and

    Eric Wilson

    or

    their

    helpful

    comments

    on

    earlier

    drafts

    of

    this

    essay.

    I

    would also

    like to thank

    Yasemin

    Ok

    or

    her

    help.

    1. For

    an excellent

    discussion

    of

    this,

    see

    Baumanl2-30.

    2.

    Locke,

    Two Treatises

    of

    Government

    : 27. There

    s, however,

    no

    necessary

    contradiction

    38

    diacritics

    30.4: 38-58

    This content downloaded from 192.43.227.18 on Tue, 17 Jun 2014 02:46:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Agmben Dead

    3/22

    toward

    something

    more

    like the

    "logical synthesis

    of

    biology

    and

    economy"

    called for

    by

    the National Socialist

    Institut

    allemand

    in

    Paris

    in

    1942

    [Agamben,

    Homo

    Sacer

    145].

    A similar

    process

    of redefinition

    s

    alreadyunderway

    n

    the field

    of

    death,

    a

    phe-

    nomenon

    that scientists and

    lawyers

    are

    having

    a harder

    and harder ime

    pinning

    down.

    Where

    once

    death

    was

    defined

    by

    the cessation of the

    movement

    of

    the heartand

    lungs,

    recent life support echnologieshave forced scientiststo define deathin termsof such

    technologies.

    Witness Doctor Norman

    Shumway's

    defense of

    the

    definition

    of

    death

    as

    braindeath:

    "I'm

    saying

    that

    anyone

    whose brain

    s

    dead is

    dead.

    It is the

    one determi-

    nant

    that

    would

    be

    universallyapplicable,

    because

    the

    brain

    s the

    one

    organ

    that can't

    be

    transplanted"

    163].

    By implication,

    f and when

    technology

    is

    developed

    thatallows

    for brain

    transplants,

    ven those

    whose

    brains

    are

    "dead"will

    be

    brought

    back

    to

    some

    kind of

    life,

    perhaps

    as

    organ

    farms for others

    who

    are less

    ambiguously

    alive.

    Giorgio

    Agamben,

    rom whose book

    Homo

    Sacer:

    Sovereign

    Power

    and

    Bare

    Life

    I take

    both

    this last

    grisly

    example

    and

    ts

    analysis, argues

    hat,

    contrary

    o

    appearances,

    such

    developments

    do

    not

    represent

    a radicalbreak

    with

    the tradition.His

    analysis

    both

    builds

    upon

    and

    corrects

    Michel

    Foucault's

    claim that

    politics

    in our time is

    constituted

    by

    disciplines

    of

    normalization

    and

    subjectification

    hat

    Foucault abels

    "bio-power."

    For

    Foucault,

    biopower

    is

    fundamentally

    modem. "What

    might

    be

    called a

    society's

    'threshold

    of

    modernity,"'

    he

    writes,

    "has

    been

    reachedwhen

    the

    life of the

    species

    is

    wagered

    on

    its own

    political

    strategies.

    For

    millennia,

    man remainedwhat

    he

    was for

    Aristotle:

    a

    living

    animal

    with the

    additional

    capacity

    for

    political

    existence;

    modem

    man is an animal whose

    politics places

    his existence

    as a

    living being

    in

    question"

    [143].

    This

    passage

    seems

    to

    imply

    not

    only

    that

    modernity

    s

    political

    in

    a different

    way

    than

    the

    previous

    millennia had

    been,

    but that

    t

    is

    more

    political,

    even

    essentially

    so. If

    politics

    was an "additional

    apacity"

    withAristotle,now

    politics

    is of ouressence,

    and life has become

    its

    object.

    Agamben

    echoes

    such

    claims at

    times,

    and

    argues,

    for

    instance,

    that

    "the

    politicization

    of

    bare life as such .

    .

    . constitutes

    the

    decisive

    event of

    modernity

    and

    signals

    a radical

    transformationof

    the

    political-philosophical categories

    of

    ancient

    thought"

    [4].

    But

    he

    also maintainsthat

    this

    transformation

    s

    made

    possible

    by

    the

    metaphysics

    of those

    very

    ancient

    categories.

    As in

    Nietzsche's

    discussion of

    nihilism,

    on

    Agamben's

    analysis, biopolitics

    fulfills the

    potential

    of

    its

    origin

    in

    turningagainst

    that

    origin.3

    Hence,

    Agambenarguesagainst

    Foucault hat ife

    in some

    sense

    always

    has

    been the definitiveobjectof politics.His argumentbegins with a review of Aristotle's

    distinction,

    n

    the first

    book of

    Politics,

    between bare life

    (to zen)

    and

    the

    good

    life

    (to

    eu

    zen):

    "we

    may

    say

    that while

    [the

    polis]

    grows

    for the sake of mere

    life,

    it

    exists for

    the sake of

    a

    good

    life"

    [1.2.8].

    Agamben

    rightly

    argues

    that

    this

    distinctionhas served

    here,

    as Locke

    also

    maintains

    that our bodies

    belong

    to

    God,

    and that our

    tacit consent

    to the

    institution

    of

    money

    takes

    us

    beyond

    the limitations

    of

    the

    initial

    orm of

    private

    property

    2:

    6,

    36,

    50].

    Not

    completely

    so,

    of

    course;

    and a

    defenderof

    UCLA,

    he

    Sandoz

    corporation,

    or the

    proponents

    of

    organ

    arming

    might

    ook

    or support

    o

    Locke's

    spoilage

    limitation: "Asmuch as

    any

    one

    can make

    use

    of

    to

    any advantage

    of life before

    t

    spoils;

    so

    much

    may

    he

    by

    his

    labourfix

    a Property n. ... Nothingwasmadeby Godfor Man tospoilor destroy"[2: 31]. One can object

    on a number

    of

    grounds

    to

    ghoulish

    proposals

    to

    develop

    "neomorts,"

    bodies

    that,

    still

    "warm,

    pulsating,

    and

    urinating"

    are

    neither

    dead

    nor

    alive,

    and

    hence

    beyond

    the

    purview

    of

    rights

    that

    mightprotect

    us

    (?)from

    being

    turned nto

    organ arms;

    but

    one can

    hardly

    cite a

    lack

    of

    either

    industriousness

    or a desire to make

    use

    of

    all that

    God

    has

    given

    us.

    3.

    It

    may

    take centuries

    or

    a

    people

    to

    experience

    the

    disgust

    with

    life

    that

    initially

    made

    them

    a

    people:

    the exhaustion

    of

    Europe

    (the

    death

    of

    God)

    is

    a

    contemporary

    vent,

    albeit one

    that

    has

    been in

    genesis

    for

    two

    thousand

    years.

    "The time has come when we

    have to

    pay for

    having

    been

    Christians

    or

    two thousand

    years:

    we are

    losing

    the center

    of

    gravity by

    virtue

    of

    which we

    lived;

    we

    are lost

    for

    a while"

    [Nietzsche,

    Will o Power

    20].

    diacritics / winter 2000

    39

    This content downloaded from 192.43.227.18 on Tue, 17 Jun 2014 02:46:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Agmben Dead

    4/22

    as the

    foundation

    of

    the

    Western radition

    of

    political philosophy,

    n that

    politics

    has

    been

    distinguished

    from

    essentially

    private enterprises

    on the

    grounds

    that

    it is

    con-

    cerned

    with

    something

    more than

    he

    perpetuation

    f

    biological

    life. Because the end

    of

    politics

    is

    different

    rom thatof

    the variousrealmsof bare

    ife,

    such as

    family

    life,

    slave

    holding,

    and

    village

    association,

    ts

    principle

    of order

    s differentas well. For

    Aristotle

    the

    "something

    more"that

    distinguishes

    the

    political

    is the realizationof the human

    capacity

    to structurea

    just

    common

    life

    in

    the

    community's

    noncoercive,

    deliberative

    reflection

    upon

    the

    question

    of

    what

    justice

    is and what concrete

    measures it

    entails:

    "Justice

    belongs

    to the

    polis;

    for

    justice,

    which

    is the determination

    f what s

    just,

    is

    an

    ordering

    of the

    political

    association"

    [Politics

    1.2.66].

    For

    all

    of

    their

    disagreements,

    the vast

    majority

    of

    contemporary oliticalphilosophers

    are united

    n

    theircommitment

    to this self-reflexive

    project,

    and

    to its

    identification

    of the

    political

    and

    the

    just.4

    Agamben,

    however,

    suggests

    that

    this

    politico-philosophicalproject

    oday

    standswith-

    out

    the

    foundations

    that Aristotle

    proposed

    for

    it,

    namely

    the

    categorical

    distinction

    between bare life and the good or political life. And this is not because an element

    foreign

    to Aristotle's schema has

    polluted

    or subverted

    t,

    but

    because

    the

    schema

    has

    deconstructed

    itself.5

    What

    s

    the

    instability

    here that would

    allow

    for this?

    When we read

    the first book

    of

    Politics

    it

    appears

    hat

    Aristotle

    is

    laying

    out

    a

    chronological

    account of the

    rise of

    the

    polis.

    Human

    beings began

    living

    in

    families,

    then

    they acquired

    laves and

    formed

    villages,

    until

    finally they

    achieved a self-sufficient

    (autarkes)

    mode

    of

    life.

    But to treat

    this

    as

    nothing

    more than a

    history

    is

    to misunderstand

    he natureof the

    boundary

    hat

    human

    beings

    cross when

    their

    community

    becomes

    self-sufficient,

    and to

    assume,

    as

    Foucault

    does in the

    passage

    cited

    above,

    that

    political

    life

    can

    be

    simply

    added on

    to

    human ife.

    Aristotle, however,

    expressly

    denies this:

    "The man who is isolated-who

    is unable to share in

    the benefits of

    political

    association,

    or has

    no need because he is

    already

    self-sufficient-is no

    part

    of the

    polis,

    and

    must thereforebe either a beast

    or

    a

    god."6

    To

    be

    truly

    humanone must

    be

    a member

    of

    apolis,

    for it

    is

    only

    as such thatone

    can

    truly speak:

    "Themere

    making

    of

    sounds

    serves to indicate

    pleasure

    and

    pain,

    and

    is thus a

    faculty

    that

    belongs

    to animals n

    general.

    .. But

    language

    serves

    to ... declare

    what

    is

    just

    and

    unjust"

    Politics 1.2.16].

    This

    conception

    of

    the

    human

    ife

    as

    not sim-

    4.

    This

    may

    seem to contradictthe

    Arendtianclaim-which

    Agambenaccepts-that

    "Soci-

    ety

    is the

    form

    in

    which the

    fact of

    mutual

    dependence or

    the sake

    of life

    and

    nothing

    else as-

    sumes

    public significance

    and

    wherethe activities connected

    with sheer survivalare

    permitted

    o

    appear

    in

    public"

    [Human

    Condition

    46].

    However,

    accepting

    as

    fundamental

    the distinction

    betweenthe

    good life

    and mere

    ife

    has

    hardlyprecluded

    iberal

    political philosophy

    rom turning

    back and

    subordinating

    he

    public

    realm to the interests

    of

    the

    private-a

    subordination hat

    redefines

    but does not

    entirely

    eliminate

    the

    categorical

    distinctionbetween

    the two. It is

    simply

    that in liberalism

    the

    "good life"

    is

    increasingly

    a

    procedural

    matter,

    one that most

    efficiently

    regulates

    the

    conflicts

    between our

    discrete

    private

    lives. The

    debate between Michael Sandel

    and John

    Rawls,

    or

    instance,

    s not over the relevance

    of

    the

    Aristotelian

    distinction,

    but

    over

    the

    definition

    and

    preconditions

    ofjustice.

    Hence each

    party

    to the

    debate understands

    himself

    to

    be

    contributing

    o the Aristotelian

    project. Compare

    Sandel

    317ff

    and Rawls

    424ff

    5.Agambendistinguisheshisanalysis roma deconstructive ne,apparentlythediscussion

    is

    uncharacteristically

    unclear)

    on the

    grounds

    that deconstruction

    allows

    itself

    to become

    en-

    tangled

    with

    paradoxes

    in an

    unhelpful

    way

    [54].

    Be

    that

    as it

    may,

    I

    am

    using

    the

    term

    quite

    loosely

    here to

    refer

    to

    a

    mode

    of

    analysis

    that

    inds

    the assertions

    it treats to

    require

    a

    logical

    structure

    (of

    say,

    binary

    oppositions

    such as

    logic

    and

    rhetoric,

    performative

    and constative

    language,

    inner and

    outer

    political life

    and bare

    life)

    that

    they

    themselves

    unravel.

    6.

    Politics 1.2.14.

    If

    this

    statement-which,

    surprisingly,

    Agamben

    does

    not

    cite-strikes

    us

    as

    hyperbolic,

    we need

    only

    recall the more

    general point

    that Book

    10

    of

    NicomacheanEthics

    ends

    with

    a call

    for

    the

    Politics because the

    particularly

    human

    aretecan

    only

    be

    realized

    within

    a

    political life.

    40

    This content downloaded from 192.43.227.18 on Tue, 17 Jun 2014 02:46:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Agmben Dead

    5/22

    ply

    a

    given

    but

    an

    achievement s definitive of

    the

    notion of humanculture.Most of us

    tend,

    however,

    to consider

    only

    the

    good

    and

    just

    life

    to

    which we

    aspire.

    Agamben

    n

    contrast

    ocuses on

    the life thatfails

    to

    achieve

    humanity;

    he

    remains,

    as it

    were,

    of

    our

    becoming

    moral,

    ust,

    and

    political.

    I

    say

    "as it

    were,"

    because "mere

    ife" cannot

    truly

    be

    exuviated.

    It

    too

    is

    human

    ife,

    though

    perhaps

    not

    fully

    so.

    In his discussionof Aristotle'sPolitics

    Agamben argues

    that

    Politics

    ...

    appears

    as the

    truly undamental

    structure

    struttura]

    of

    Western

    metaphysics nsofar

    as it

    occupies

    the threshold

    soglia]

    on which the relation

    between

    the

    living

    being

    and

    the

    logos

    is

    realized

    [si

    compie].

    In

    the

    "politicization"of

    bare

    life-the metaphysical

    task

    par

    excellence-the hu-

    manity

    of living

    man is

    decided

    [si decide].

    ... There s

    politics

    because man

    is

    the

    living being

    who,

    in

    language,

    separates

    and

    opposes

    himself

    to

    his

    own

    bare

    life

    [nuda vita]

    and,

    at the

    same

    time,

    maintains

    himself

    n relation o that

    bare life in an inclusive exclusion[un' esclusioneinclusiva]. [8]7

    "Threshold"s a word that occurs

    again

    and

    again

    in

    Agamben's

    text,

    and

    it

    invariably

    signifies

    a

    passage

    that

    cannot

    be

    completed,

    a distinction that can be neither

    main-

    tained nor

    eliminated.8

    The

    fundamental

    political

    distinctionbetween bare life and the

    good,

    just

    life lived

    in

    accordance

    with the

    logos

    proposes

    humanity

    as a

    project,

    one

    of

    self-overcoming.

    But this

    project,

    as

    such,

    relies

    upon

    "theexclusion

    (which

    is

    simulta-

    neously

    an

    inclusion)

    of bare life

    [una

    esclusione

    (che

    e,

    nella stessa

    misura,

    un'im-

    plicazione)

    della nuda

    vita]"

    [7].

    Bare

    life

    is

    a

    necessarypart

    of

    the

    good

    life,

    in

    thatthe

    good

    life

    is

    both what

    bare

    ife

    is not

    and whatbare ife

    becomes,

    "as f

    politics

    were the

    place

    in

    which life had to

    transform

    tself

    into

    good

    life and in which what had

    to

    be

    politicized

    were

    always already

    bare ife"

    [7].

    This is not a dialectic

    between two com-

    parable

    moments

    of the

    human,

    or it is

    only political

    life

    that

    s

    truly

    ived in

    language,

    that

    can

    truly

    speak.

    Bare life

    is

    mute, undifferentiated,

    nd

    stripped

    of both the

    gener-

    ality

    and

    the

    specificity

    that

    anguage

    makes

    possible.

    If

    it is

    relatedand

    compared

    and

    evaluated,

    that

    is

    always

    in the

    terms and

    in the service

    of

    what it is not:

    political

    life.

    But

    since

    political

    life

    defines itself in termsof its

    genesis

    from and its

    nonidentity

    with

    bare

    life,

    political

    life

    is defined

    by

    its

    relationwith the nonrelational.9

    Exteriority

    ..

    7.

    On

    politics

    as

    metaphysics, compare

    44

    ff.,

    182,

    and the discussion

    of Heidegger

    and

    Levinas at

    150-53.

    8. Homo Sacer is divided into three

    parts,

    with

    an

    additional

    introduction.The

    irst

    is de-

    voted

    to

    the nature

    of

    sovereignty,

    he

    second

    to

    that

    of

    the Homo

    Sacer

    of

    the

    title,

    and the third

    to

    "the

    Camp

    as

    Biopolitical Paradigm

    of

    the Modern.

    "

    Each

    of

    these ends with

    a section entitled

    "Threshold"

    Soglia). Agamben

    does

    not announce

    this,

    but I

    believe the word is

    derived

    rom

    and meant

    to

    refer

    back to these

    lines,

    which are

    ound

    in

    the

    irst

    "Threshold":"Inthe words

    of

    Benveniste,

    to render he victim

    sacred,

    it

    is

    necessary

    'to

    separate itfrom

    the world

    of

    the

    living,

    it is

    necessary

    to

    cross the

    threshold that

    separates

    the two universes: this is the aim

    of

    the

    killing'"

    [66].

    If

    this is

    so,

    each

    part

    of

    the bookends in the

    "no-man's-land"

    159]

    between

    life

    and death. Each

    therefore

    serves as

    a

    different

    path

    to the same

    goal,

    that

    of

    the

    confusion

    of

    politics

    and

    life. Compare

    his

    conception

    of

    the

    threshold

    with Jean-Luc

    Nancy's

    discussion

    of

    Caravaggio

    s Death

    of

    the

    Virgin

    n his

    essay

    "On

    the

    Threshold":"Death: we

    are

    never

    there,

    we are

    always

    there. Inside and

    outside,

    at once"

    [115].

    9.

    Compare

    24

    ("The

    sovereign exception

    is thus the

    figure

    in

    which

    singularity

    is

    repre-

    sented as

    such,

    which is

    to

    say, insofar

    as

    it

    is

    unrepresentable"),

    9

    ("the

    simple positing

    of

    relation with

    the

    nonrelational"),

    60

    ("the

    relationshipof

    abandonment

    s

    not a

    relation"),

    and

    110

    ("The

    ban

    is

    essentially

    ... the

    power of

    maintaining

    tself

    in

    relation

    to

    something

    presup-

    posed

    as

    nonrelational").

    diacritics /

    winter 2000

    41

    This content downloaded from 192.43.227.18 on Tue, 17 Jun 2014 02:46:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Agmben Dead

    6/22

    is

    truly

    the innermost enterof the

    political system,

    andthe

    political system

    lives off it"

    [36].

    This accountof the

    paradoxical

    nclusive exclusion of bare life in the

    metaphysics

    of

    politics

    can be

    seen as

    a

    more radicalversion of

    Arendt's

    paradoxical

    claim

    in

    The

    Originsof

    Totalitarianism

    hat

    "a

    man

    who

    is

    nothing

    but a man has lost the

    very

    quali-

    ties which make it

    possible

    for other

    people

    to treat

    him as

    a

    man"

    [300].

    Similarly,

    Agamben's

    more radical account

    of

    the

    logic

    at work here has obvious affinities with

    and debts to

    Hegel's analysis

    of the law of

    identity

    as a

    self-contradictory rinciple

    hat,

    as

    such,

    proves

    to

    be

    a

    law

    of

    contradiction:hose who assert

    he

    principle

    "A=

    A...

    do

    not see that

    n

    this

    very

    assertion

    hey

    arethemselves

    saying

    that

    dentity

    s

    different;

    or

    they

    are

    saying

    that

    dentity

    s

    different

    rom

    difference;

    ince

    this

    must at the same

    time

    be admitted o

    be

    the natureof

    identity,

    heir assertion

    mplies

    that

    identity,

    not exter-

    nally,

    but

    in

    its own

    self,

    in

    its

    very

    nature,

    s

    this,

    to be different"

    Hegel

    413].

    The

    resulting concept

    of

    negation

    is for

    Hegel

    the

    engine

    of

    history,

    and as such

    it

    allows

    him to reconcile his claim thathistory progresseswith the evident fact that the most

    glorious

    and

    praiseworthy

    empires

    are

    inevitably

    ground

    under

    in

    the course

    of

    that

    progress.Negation

    as the

    dialectical and historical movement

    of

    Reason

    thereby

    ulti-

    mately

    produces

    or reveals itself to be a

    harmonious,

    rational

    totality.

    In

    contrast,

    on

    Agamben's

    account,

    the

    Aufhebung

    of

    politics

    is never achieved:bare life

    and

    political

    life are never

    reconciled,

    and

    political

    life's

    every

    attempt-the attempt

    that defines

    political

    life-to mediate ts own

    relationship

    with

    the

    life that it

    is

    not fails in

    the end.

    More

    significant

    than the differences between

    Agamben

    and

    Hegel

    is

    the fact that for

    both

    it is

    the movement

    hrough negation

    that

    is

    essential,

    not the fiction of

    a

    static

    result.

    Hence,

    on

    Agamben'saccount,politics mustagain andagain

    enact

    its internal

    distinctionfrom bare life.

    It must

    repeatedly

    define

    itself

    through

    he

    negation

    of

    bare

    life-a

    negation

    that can

    always

    take

    the

    form of

    death.'1

    The

    analysis

    of the

    metaphysical

    movement of the

    living being

    "into"

    anguage

    that

    undergirds

    hese claims has been an

    ongoing

    concern of

    Agamben's."

    His earlier

    Language

    and

    Death:

    ThePlace

    of Negativity

    nvestigates

    he

    metaphysical

    onnection

    between

    human

    mortality

    and the human

    capacity

    for

    language particularly

    s it is de-

    lineated

    n

    Heidegger

    and

    Hegel.

    Agambenbegins

    the book

    by

    citing

    the former's

    claim

    (from

    On the

    Way

    to

    Language)

    that "Mortalsare

    they

    who can

    experience

    death as

    death. Animals cannot do so. But animals

    cannot

    speak

    either.

    The

    essential relation

    between deathand

    language

    flashes beforeus, but remains

    unthought"

    xi]. He

    goes

    on

    to

    try

    to "think" his relation

    hrough

    a considerationof the

    originary

    natureof

    negativ-

    ity

    in

    Heidegger's thought

    of

    Da-sein

    and

    Hegel's thought

    of the

    Diese,

    and

    argues

    hat

    "both

    he

    'faculty'

    for

    language

    and the

    'faculty'

    for

    death,

    inasmuchas

    they open

    for

    humanity

    he most

    properdwelling place

    [la

    sua

    dimora

    pia propria],

    reveal and dis-

    close

    this same

    dwelling place

    as

    always alreadypermeatedby

    and founded n

    negativ-

    ity"

    [xii].

    There

    is,

    Agamben argues,

    a

    structural

    parallel

    between

    the

    ambiguous

    place

    of

    death

    within the human ife and the

    place

    of indicationwithin

    language.

    Each serves as

    a limit or thresholdwhich one can place neither within nor withoutthe life or system

    10.

    Indeed,

    on

    Hegel's

    account it must: "nichtdas

    Leben,

    das sich

    vor

    dem

    Tode

    cheuntund

    vor

    der

    Verwiistung

    ein

    bewahrt,

    onderndas ihn

    ertaigt

    und n ihmsich

    erhdilt,

    st das Lebendes

    Geistes"

    [qtd.

    in

    Schnaidelbach

    6].

    11.

    In an earlier

    work

    Agamben

    writes

    of

    "an

    unwrittenbook"

    on

    this

    theme,

    The Human

    Voice,

    of

    which his writtenworks

    after

    1977 serve as the

    prologue

    and

    afterwords.

    n

    this unwrit-

    ten

    work

    there

    are

    "numerous

    rafts" transcribing

    he

    passage

    in Politics where

    Aristotle

    bases

    man's

    political

    nature

    upon

    his

    ability

    to

    speak

    ofjustice

    and

    injustice

    see

    Agamben, nfancy

    and

    History

    3 and

    7-8].

    42

    This content downloaded from 192.43.227.18 on Tue, 17 Jun 2014 02:46:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Agmben Dead

    7/22

    that

    it defines. Death is

    something

    ike

    an

    ostensive

    definitionwith which

    one seeks to

    pick

    out the

    nonlinguistic

    eality

    that

    anguage

    discusses and hat

    makes

    anguage

    mean-

    ingful.

    Just as

    "the limit of

    language always

    falls

    within

    language"

    such

    that it "is al-

    ways

    contained

    within as a

    negative,"

    so death

    both

    is

    and

    is

    not "an event of

    life."'2

    Because

    of this structural

    arallel,

    death

    assumes

    a

    privileged place

    in

    the

    logic

    of

    the

    "meaning"

    of humanlife. As in the

    passage

    cited from

    Heidegger

    above, and as in

    Heidegger's

    early

    insistence that the authenticor

    properresponse

    to

    human

    mortality

    entails

    heeding

    the silent call of

    conscience,

    death shows what

    language

    can never

    say,

    and in so

    doing

    serves as the revelation

    of

    the

    negative ground

    of the

    human.'3

    We

    might

    say

    thatdeathbecomes

    beautiful.

    The

    two

    momentsof

    the

    "speaking

    nimal"

    are

    thereby

    cast into an

    endless

    struggle:

    "from he dawn of Greek

    thought,

    he

    human

    experience

    of

    language

    (that

    s,

    the

    experience

    of the

    human

    as both

    living

    and

    speaking,

    a

    natural

    and a

    logical being)

    has

    appeared

    n

    the

    tragic

    spectacle

    divided

    by

    an

    unresolvable

    conflict."The

    form this conflict

    takes

    is thatof the sacrificialviolence that

    serves

    as the

    ungroundedgroundof all praxis[LanguageandDeath 58-62, 88, 105-06].

    Homo Sacer

    advancesthis

    analysis

    in at least two

    ways:

    in its reflections

    upon

    the

    kind of

    "life" hat s involved

    in

    this

    process,

    and

    n

    its consideration

    f the

    distinctively

    political aspect

    of this movement.In

    Language

    and

    Death

    the

    metaphysical

    movement

    into a

    relationship

    with the

    logos

    does

    not

    essentially

    involve

    the

    living

    body,

    nor does

    Agamben

    spend

    much

    time

    drawing

    out

    the

    implications

    of this

    metaphysics

    for the

    body.14

    he names

    Foucault,

    Arendt,

    and

    Schmitt--each

    of

    which

    figureprominently

    n

    Homo

    Sacer-do

    not

    appear,

    and when

    Agamben

    does

    speak

    of the

    practical

    mplica-

    tions of

    metaphysics

    that

    "which

    enacts

    [compie]

    he

    experience

    [1'esperienza]

    merely

    shown

    [mostrare]by logic" [Language

    and Death

    88]

    he

    speaks

    of "ethics"

    epeatedly,

    and

    only

    two or three

    times

    of

    "politics."'5

    Nonetheless,

    the

    development

    and extension

    of

    the

    analysis

    does

    not alter ts

    fundamental

    tructure.

    12.

    Language

    and Death

    17 and

    Wittgenstein,

    Tractatus

    Logico-Philosophicus

    6.4311. Both

    here

    and

    in his

    appendix

    to

    The

    Coming

    Community,

    Agamben

    is

    influenced by

    the

    early

    Wittgenstein's

    nderstanding

    of

    the

    mystical

    status

    of

    ethics and his related insistence that the

    ability

    to

    say (sagen)

    things

    in

    language

    rests

    upon

    anguage'sability

    to

    show

    (zeichen)

    things.

    As

    David Pears

    puts

    it,

    "language

    cannot contain

    an

    analysis of

    the

    conditions

    of

    its own

    applica-

    tion"[11].

    13.

    "And

    o what is

    one

    summoned?

    To one's own self.

    ....

    The call is

    lacking

    any

    kind

    of

    utterance.

    t

    does not even come

    to

    words,

    and

    yet

    is not

    at

    all obscureand

    indefinite.

    Conscience

    speaks olely

    and

    constantly

    n

    the modeof silence"

    Heidegger

    Being

    andTime

    252;

    cf

    Lan-

    guage

    andDeath

    54-62].

    14. See

    Language

    and Death:

    "Metaphysics

    s not

    simply

    that

    thought

    hat thinks he

    experi-

    ence

    of language

    on the basis

    of

    an

    (animal)

    voice,

    but

    rather,

    t

    always already

    thinks his

    expe-

    rience on the basis

    of

    the

    negative

    dimension

    of

    a

    Voice"

    61].

    1

    should note that this statement s

    phrased

    as

    a

    conditional.

    However

    the context makes it clear that it is

    Agamben's

    considered

    view,

    as

    it

    is

    on this basis that he concludes that

    Heidegger ails

    in the

    end

    to

    escape metaphys-

    ics-a conclusion

    that

    is

    hardly insignificant,

    providing

    as it does the

    justification or

    much

    of

    Agamben's

    own

    attempt

    o move

    beyond

    Heidegger

    Thatsaid, it remains rue that his

    attempt

    o

    do

    this

    is

    in

    many ways

    a

    working

    out

    of

    the

    problem of

    the

    place of

    the animal in

    fundamental

    ontology

    and

    the

    critique

    of

    metaphysics,

    a

    problem

    hat s laid out

    in

    admirabledetail

    by

    Derrida

    in the sixth

    chapter

    of

    his Of

    Spirit:

    Heidegger

    and

    the

    Question.

    15.

    See

    Language

    and Death

    86-88,

    91. This

    distinction,

    while

    significant,

    should not be

    exaggerated,given

    Agamben's

    ommitmento the

    Heideggerian

    nterpretation f

    "ethos"

    as nam-

    ing

    "theabode

    of

    man" rather than the

    individual's

    character or habit.

    Compare

    Language

    and

    Death 93 and

    Heidegger

    "Letteron Humanism"

    258.

    For

    evidence

    that

    Agamben's

    conception

    of

    the ethical nonetheless retains

    amiliar

    connotations

    of privacy

    as

    opposed

    to the

    publicity

    of

    the

    political,

    see

    Language

    and

    Death

    107.

    diacritics

    /

    winter 2000

    43

    This content downloaded from 192.43.227.18 on Tue, 17 Jun 2014 02:46:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Agmben Dead

    8/22

    The termsof

    this

    discussion

    make

    plainAgamben's

    debt

    to

    Heidegger.

    n so

    doing,

    they

    open

    his

    analysis

    to the threatof

    quiet

    dismissal

    by

    political

    theorists,

    many

    of

    whom are

    wearied

    by

    the abstractness

    nd the

    density

    of

    this

    language.

    In

    this

    regard

    t

    is

    crucial

    to

    note how

    well

    Agamben's

    analysis

    accounts

    or

    otherwiseobscurefeatures

    of canonical texts that

    he himself

    ignores.

    We

    might begin by

    comparing

    he

    passages

    fromAristotle

    upon

    which

    Agamben

    focuses with Socrates's

    strikingly

    similarclaimin

    the

    Crito

    that "the

    really important hing

    is not to

    live,

    but to live well." This

    claim

    is

    in

    fact the

    central

    move

    in

    Socrates's

    ustification

    of his

    active

    participation

    n

    his own

    execution.

    He in otherwords

    enacts

    the

    sacrifice

    of

    bare ife that

    he

    prioritization

    f

    the

    good

    life entails. Aristotle's use of this formulation o describe a

    political

    life

    that

    is

    meant

    to

    endure on both the

    level

    of

    biology

    and virtue is

    obviously

    more

    problem-

    atic-a fact

    that

    may go

    some

    way

    toward

    explaining

    Aristotle's

    own

    celebration

    of the

    kalos death.

    Nor is this the

    only

    such

    moment

    n

    the Platonic

    corpus.

    We

    might

    consideras well

    the second book of Plato'sRepublic:this gives us as cleara pictureof politics as the

    metaphysical

    movementdescribed

    by Agamben

    as

    any

    other,

    generating

    as

    it

    does a

    just

    city

    from

    the

    inadequacies

    of

    Adeimantus's

    "city

    in

    speech,"

    a

    city

    whose

    exclusive

    focus

    upon

    the satisfactionof

    bodily

    need

    prohibits

    Socrates

    and his

    companions

    rom

    discerning

    the natureand

    origin

    of

    justice.

    In

    the first book of the

    Republic

    ustice

    is

    tentatively

    associatedwith tradeandwith

    interstate onflict

    [332e, 333a].

    Trade

    s

    present

    in

    Adeimantus's

    city,

    as is at least the

    abstract

    possibility

    of

    war

    [372b],

    and

    so

    one

    might

    assume that

    justice

    will

    be

    as well.

    Yet Socrates hesitates to

    say

    this.

    When he

    asks "where .. would

    justice

    and

    injustice

    be"

    [371e]

    in

    such

    a

    city,

    Adeimantusre-

    plies,

    "'I can't

    think,

    Socrates,...

    unless it's somewhere n

    some need these men have

    of

    one

    another"

    372a].

    Though

    this

    sounds

    very

    much like the

    picture

    we

    ultimately

    get,

    in

    which

    justice

    is a matter

    of

    the

    internalstructure f

    the

    city,

    where each

    person

    does his

    own,

    proper

    ask,

    and each

    particular

    inds its

    meaning

    and its

    satisfaction

    n

    the balanced

    whole,

    Socrates

    hardly

    embraces

    Adeimantus's

    entative,

    nitial formula-

    tion with enthusiasm.

    "'Perhaps

    what

    you say

    is

    fine,"'

    he

    replies.

    "'It

    must

    really

    be

    considered and we mustn't back

    away"'

    [372a].

    The

    considerations hat

    follow,

    how-

    ever,

    are

    entirely

    circumscribed

    by

    the

    guiding assumptions

    of the

    city's

    founder

    con-

    cerning

    need and

    satisfaction,

    and

    they produce

    nothing

    more thanan almost

    comically

    banal list

    of

    the material

    arrangements

    f

    the

    city,

    its

    procreation

    nd ts

    production

    and

    consumptionof "bread,wine, clothing,and shoes"[372a].

    It

    is

    at

    this

    point

    that Glaucon oses

    patience

    and

    objects

    thatthis

    is no

    human

    city

    at all. When Socrates akes

    up

    Glaucon's

    suggestion

    that

    they

    must consider

    a

    city

    that

    is driven

    by

    the

    desire to

    satisfy

    more than the needs of

    mere

    life,

    he notes

    that

    "in

    considering

    such a

    city

    ... we could

    probably

    see in what

    way

    justice

    and

    injustice

    naturallygrow

    in

    cities"

    [372e].

    Why

    have

    they

    not been able to

    do

    so

    up

    to now?

    Why

    does Socrates

    mply

    that

    Adeimantus'sanswerwas

    inaccurate,

    because

    they

    were not

    in

    a

    position

    to answerthe

    question

    of

    justice?

    The answer s that he has

    silently accepted

    Glaucon's criticisms

    of the

    city

    of mere

    life.

    This

    acceptance

    s

    implied

    when Socrates

    says of pigs: "'This animalwasn't in ourearliercity-there was no need-but in this

    one

    there will be

    need

    of it in

    addition"'

    [373c].

    For

    Socrates to

    say

    this of the

    city

    Glauconhas moments before termed "a

    city

    of sows" would

    appear

    to be an ironic

    confirmationof Glaucon's

    objection:

    it is

    unlikely

    that Socrates believes

    pork

    to be

    necessary

    to the feverish

    life

    of

    luxury.

    t is more

    likely

    thathe

    says pigs

    wereunneces-

    sary

    in

    the

    "healthy"city

    because,

    as Glaucon

    claims,

    the citizens themselves were

    pigs.

    This silent

    agreement

    eads

    Socratesto

    help

    in

    the constitution

    of

    Glaucon's

    "fe-

    verish"

    city,

    where the

    aspiration

    o

    satisfy

    morethan the needs of life will

    require

    he

    sacrifice of life in war.It is this

    city

    which

    ultimately

    ssues forththe

    just city

    which,

    as

    44

    This content downloaded from 192.43.227.18 on Tue, 17 Jun 2014 02:46:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Agmben Dead

    9/22

    a

    just

    city, literally

    breeds

    its

    inhabitants--that

    s to

    say,

    a

    city

    that

    self-consciously

    reenacts

    the

    genesis

    of

    the

    just

    life from bare life.

    Indeed,

    Socrates calls for more than

    simple

    breeding:

    the

    political

    "artof

    judging"

    is in fact made

    possible

    by

    an "artof

    medicine,"

    he

    practice

    of which involves

    that he doctor"let die the ones whose bodies

    are

    [corrupt],

    and

    the ones whose souls

    have bad naturesand

    are

    incurable,

    hey

    them-

    selves will kill"

    [409e-410].

    Socrateshere

    openly

    accepts

    thathis

    biopolitics

    must at

    the same time

    be a

    thanatopolitics.

    Here,

    perhaps

    more

    clearly

    than in the

    few lines

    from

    Aristotle

    upon

    which

    Agamben

    focuses,

    we

    can

    see that Arendt s both

    exactly

    right

    and

    exactly wrong

    when she

    argues

    that

    "politics

    s never

    for

    the sake of

    life."16

    It

    is the movement

    from

    bare

    life to

    political

    life that defines

    both

    bare

    life and

    political

    life."

    Politics thus

    entails the constant

    negotiation

    of the thresholdbetween

    itself and

    the bare ife that s both included

    within and

    excluded

    from

    its

    body.

    But such

    a threshold

    s

    hopelessly

    unstable,

    as is

    signaled

    by

    the

    fact

    that

    politics

    is both the

    passage

    from bare life to itself and what

    lies

    beyond

    this

    passage."1

    The titles of the

    16.

    The Human

    Condition

    37. For a more

    contemporary

    example

    of

    the relevance

    of

    Agamben'sanalysis,

    consider William

    Connolly's

    claim that

    "Identity

    equires

    difference

    n or-

    der

    to

    be,

    and it converts

    difference

    nto otherness in order

    to

    secure its

    own

    self-certainty."

    On

    the

    face

    of

    it

    it would

    appear

    that

    Connolly'sanalysis

    of

    the

    paradoxes of

    political identity

    is

    limited

    to a discussion

    of

    our

    need

    to

    distinguish

    ourselves

    from

    other

    individuals

    and

    groups

    without

    reifying

    that distinction

    by claiming

    that the other is so

    different

    as to be

    inferior

    or

    threatening.

    Connolly

    however

    has

    remindedme

    that

    his

    analysis

    here

    of self

    and other is

    open

    to

    a

    third

    element,

    that

    of life:

    "There

    s more in

    my

    life

    than

    any official

    definition

    of identity

    can

    express.

    I

    am not exhausted

    by my identity."

    Significantly

    his

    greater

    me

    is

    not

    me: "thisabun-

    dance is in me but is neithermenormine";hence it "canhelpme to recognizeand attendto the

    claims

    of

    the

    other

    in

    myself

    "

    On

    the

    face

    of

    it the structure

    of

    this

    paradox

    would

    appear

    to

    exactly

    replicate

    that

    ofAgamben's

    bare

    life,

    which both is

    and

    is not a

    moment

    of

    the

    life

    of

    the

    polis.

    Wemust then ask whether he

    acknowledgment

    f

    a

    life

    that

    "I"

    live but that is not

    "mine"

    can avoid

    the

    metaphysicalquandaries

    ofAgamben

    s

    analysis

    [see

    Connolly

    64,

    120].

    17.

    Agambenbegins

    by identifying

    bare

    life

    with

    zoe,

    "the

    simple act

    of

    living

    common

    to

    all

    living beings,

    "

    as

    opposed

    to

    bios,

    "which

    in

    ancient

    Greek]

    indicated

    the

    form

    or

    way of

    living proper

    to an

    individual

    or a

    group"

    [1,

    4].

    But in

    the

    passage

    from

    Aristotle's

    Politics

    upon

    which he

    places

    such

    importance,

    he

    distinction

    between

    bare

    life

    and

    political

    life

    is between

    two variants

    of

    zoe.

    Moreover,

    on

    88

    "simple

    natural

    ife"

    ("la

    semplice

    vita

    naturale")

    is

    con-

    trastedwith "lifeexposedto death(bareorsacredlife)

    "

    ("la vitaespostaalla morte[la nuda vita

    o

    vita

    sacra]").

    Presumably

    this

    is

    because

    simple

    natural

    life

    is

    not in

    itself

    in relation with

    political

    life,

    and

    sacred

    life

    is

    defined

    by precisely

    that

    relationship.

    This is corroborated

    by

    Agamben

    s

    assertion

    on 90 that sacred

    life

    is "neither

    political

    bios nor natural zoe" but rather

    "the

    zone

    of

    indistinction

    n

    which

    zoe

    and bios

    constituteeach

    other in

    including

    and

    excluding

    each

    other"

    [and

    see

    106,

    109].

    If

    we take this

    process

    as the

    metaphysical

    movement

    of politics,

    this seems to

    come

    closest

    to

    Agamben

    s

    considered

    view;

    but

    it

    is

    clearly

    incompatible

    with the

    claims

    made earlier in the book.

    It

    is

    also

    unclear

    how

    consistent

    t

    is with

    Agamben

    s

    suggestions

    that

    his bare

    life

    is

    or

    can be

    a

    form of

    "pure

    ife"

    ("pura

    vita")

    [171].

    Nonetheless,

    many of

    the

    confusions

    that seem

    to

    plague Agamben's

    use

    of

    the term "bare

    life"

    are

    only

    superficial:

    on

    114-15,

    for

    instance,

    he writes that

    "Sacredness s

    a line

    of flight

    still

    present

    in

    contemporary

    politics, a line that is movinginto zones increasinglyvast and dark, to the point of ultimately

    coinciding

    with the

    biological

    life

    [vita

    biologica]

    of

    the

    citizens."

    This

    might

    appear

    to

    repeat

    the

    same

    contradiction

    o

    which

    I

    have

    just

    pointed;

    but

    this

    appearance

    is

    deceiving:

    it is be-

    cause

    biopolitics

    in

    the

    form of

    sacred

    life

    defines

    both bare

    life

    and

    political life

    that

    these

    definitions

    can

    change,

    and

    even,

    as in

    modernity,

    ollapse

    into one another

    18. The

    instability of

    the distinction between

    political

    and

    apolitical life

    may already

    be

    signaled

    in Aristotle's ext: This entire discussion is an

    explication

    and

    defense of

    his claim

    that,

    pace

    Plato 's

    Statesman,

    "It s a mistake o believe that the 'statesman'

    s the

    same as

    the

    monarch

    of

    a

    kingdom,

    or the

    manager of

    a

    household,

    or

    the master

    of

    a

    number

    of

    slaves"

    [1.1.2].

    The

    order

    of

    the

    family

    is not "the

    determination

    of

    what is

    just"

    but the

    rule

    of

    the

    father

    and hus-

    diacritics /

    winter

    2000

    45

    This content downloaded from 192.43.227.18 on Tue, 17 Jun 2014 02:46:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Agmben Dead

    10/22

    three

    parts

    of

    Agamben's

    book

    mark he

    different

    momentsof its

    unraveling:

    "The

    Logic

    of

    Sovereignty,"

    "Homo

    Sacer,"

    and

    "The

    Camp

    as

    Biopolitical

    Paradigm

    of the

    Mod-

    em."

    Withthe rise

    of

    sovereignty

    we witness the constitutionof

    a

    political authority

    hat

    corresponds

    o the

    ambiguities

    of this thresholdmore

    closely

    then

    did the

    polis.

    Sover-

    eignty,

    on this

    account,

    s not

    simply

    a

    momentof

    the

    rise of the

    nation-state,

    ut

    instead

    an

    expression

    of the inner

    dynamics

    of the

    logic

    of

    politics. Agamben

    here follows Carl

    Schmitt's

    analysis

    of the

    sovereign

    as

    "he who

    decides

    on the

    exception"

    [5].19

    As

    Agamben

    notes,

    the word

    "exception"

    l'eccezione

    or

    die

    Aus-nahme),

    "according

    o

    its

    etymological

    root"refers o

    what

    s

    "taken utside

    (ex-capere),

    andnot

    simply

    excluded"

    [18].

    The

    sovereign,

    in other words, has the

    legal authority

    o decide who shall be re-

    moved

    from the

    purview

    of

    law,

    as

    in a

    state of martial aw

    or

    the Schmittianstate of

    emergency.Sovereignty

    s

    the

    law's thresholdwith the

    nonlegal;

    as Schmitt

    writes,

    t is

    "a borderline

    oncept

    . ..

    one

    pertaining

    o the outermost

    phere"

    5].20

    It is the

    point

    at

    which the law enters nto relationwith that which has no

    legal standing.

    Inidentifying he thresholdbetween thelegal andthenonlegal, sovereigntydefines

    them both. This is

    perhaps

    clearer

    in

    Schmitt's

    text than in

    Agamben's.

    "There

    s,"

    Schmitt

    writes,

    "no

    norm

    applicable

    o chaos. For a

    legal

    order o make

    sense,

    a

    normal

    situationmust

    exist,

    and he is

    sovereign

    who

    definitively

    decides

    whether his normal

    situationexists"

    [13].

    A

    state of

    emergency

    s

    the

    product

    of

    the

    collapse

    of the

    normal

    order;

    but the normal order

    s

    only

    the

    absence of a state of

    emergency.21

    Agamben's

    gloss

    on this

    is

    that

    The

    exception

    [1'eccezione]

    does

    not subtract

    itself

    from

    the rule

    [regola];

    rather,

    he

    rule,suspending tself, gives

    rise to

    the

    exceptionand,maintaining

    itself

    in relation to the

    exception, irst

    constitutes

    itself

    as a

    rule. .

    .

    . The

    sovereign

    decision

    [La

    decisione

    sovrana]

    of

    the

    exception

    is the

    orginary

    juridico-political

    structure

    struttura]

    on the basis

    of

    which what

    is

    included

    in the

    uridical

    orderand what is excluded

    rom

    it

    acquire

    their

    meaning.

    [

    18-

    19].

    He

    concludes

    from this that "What

    emerges

    in

    the limit

    figure

    [figura-limite]

    s the

    radical crisis of

    every possibility

    of

    clearly

    distinguishing

    between

    membership

    and

    inclusion,

    between what s outside andwhat is

    inside,

    between

    exception

    andrule"

    25].

    Oncethe rule

    acknowledges

    hat t

    gives

    rise to

    exceptions

    for which it cannot

    egislate,

    every

    case

    can,

    in

    principle,

    be understood n these terms.

    The

    only way

    to

    avoid this

    band,

    who is

    analogous

    to a slave-owner

    and

    a monarch.

    In

    all three

    cases, domination,

    not

    deliberation,

    s the

    orderingprinciple, ust

    as

    the end is not

    the

    good life,

    but the

    perpetuationof

    life.

    However

    in the

    ace of

    all

    of

    this

    Aristotle asserts that our

    perceptions

    of good

    and

    evil

    and

    just

    and

    unjust

    make

    up

    both

    "a

    amily

    and

    a

    polis"

    [1.2.12].

    19. It

    might

    be better

    to

    say

    that

    Agamben

    here

    appropriates

    chmitt,

    or

    it is

    certainly

    true

    that

    his

    borrowings

    rom

    Heidegger Hegel,

    Schmitt,

    t al.

    pursue

    a common heme hat is

    defined

    more

    by

    Agamben

    than

    by

    his sources.

    20. For a

    very

    similar discussion

    (albeit

    one conductedon a less

    metaphysical

    plane) of

    the

    rise

    of sovereignty,

    ee Bartelson.

    Here,

    as in

    Agamben's

    discussion,

    the

    rise

    of

    sovereignty

    en-

    tails the

    destabilization

    of

    "the

    very

    divide

    that

    previously

    separated

    the inside

    of republican

    politicsfrom

    its moreanarchic

    outside,

    "

    a

    destabilization

    n

    which

    "whatformerly

    was

    relegated

    to the outside now moves

    into the

    very

    center

    of

    political

    action and

    understanding"

    330-31;

    compare

    Homo Sacer

    35-36].

    21.

    It

    should be clear that

    this

    does not

    necessarily

    repeat

    Bodin

    s

    claim that

    sovereignty

    s

    the

    source

    of

    law,

    where

    law is

    defined

    as command.

    The

    source

    of

    the law need not be the

    sovereign;

    but

    if

    the

    sovereign

    does decide

    on the

    exception,

    then,

    in so

    doing,

    it

    decides

    on

    the

    norm as well

    [see

    Bodin

    38,

    51].

    46

    This content downloaded from 192.43.227.18 on Tue, 17 Jun 2014 02:46:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Agmben Dead

    11/22

    conclusion

    is

    to

    argue

    that,

    even

    in

    those cases where the rule cannot

    legislate,

    it

    still

    does

    legislate

    in

    some

    impoverished

    ense. One would have

    to

    argue,

    hat

    s,

    that

    excep-

    tional cases are

    clearly

    defined

    as such

    by

    the

    rule.

    But

    this is in

    effect

    to

    deny

    the

    reality

    of

    the

    exception

    and

    the need of the

    legal

    order or a

    sovereign

    decision

    upon

    it.

    With

    the rise of

    sovereignty

    we

    witness

    the

    rise

    of

    a form of life that

    corresponds

    o

    it. "Thesovereignsphere[sfera] is the spherein which it is permitted o kill without

    committing

    homicide

    and without

    celebrating

    a

    sacrifice

    [sacrificio],

    and sacred life

    [sacra]-that

    is,

    life that

    may

    be killed

    but

    not sacrificed-is the life that

    has been

    captured

    n this

    sphere"

    83].

    Agamben

    does

    not

    define the sacred n terms

    of

    "what s

    set

    apart

    or

    worship

    of the

    deity."

    He

    is

    interested n the more

    fundamental

    question

    of

    the

    logic

    of

    sacrifice

    (from

    Latin

    sacrificium,

    from

    sacr-, sacer,

    holy,

    cursed)

    as re-

    vealed

    in

    the

    life that is

    sacred

    (from

    Latin

    sacrare,

    also

    from

    sacr-,

    sacer).

    What

    Agamben

    terms

    sacred

    life

    is,

    like the

    sovereign,

    both within and without the

    legal

    order

    (or,

    as its

    etymology suggests,

    both

    holy

    and

    cursed).

    It is

    inside the

    legal

    order

    insofaras its death can be allowedby thatorder;but it is outsideit insofaras its death

    can constitute

    neither a homicide

    nor a

    sacrifice. But where

    sovereignty

    is

    a

    form of

    power

    that

    occupies

    this

    threshold,

    sacred

    ife is

    nothing

    more than a

    life

    that

    occupies

    this

    threshold,

    a life that s

    excluded and included

    n the

    political

    order.Here this takes

    the form

    not,

    as

    in

    Aristotle,

    of

    a

    metaphysical

    puzzle,

    but

    ratherof

    a mute

    helplessness

    in the face

    of

    death. "Sacredness

    s

    ...

    the

    originary

    orm of the

    inclusion

    of

    bare life

    [nuda

    vita]

    in

    the

    judicial

    order,

    and the

    syntagm

    homo

    sacer names

    something

    ike

    the

    originary political'

    relation,

    which

    is to

    say,

    bare

    life

    insofar as

    it

    operates

    n

    an inclu-

    sive exclusion

    as the referentof the

    sovereign

    decision"

    [85].

    This

    is the

    explicit

    revela-

    tion of the

    metaphysical

    requirement

    that

    politics

    establish a relation with the

    nonrelational

    cf.

    note

    8].

    Indeed,

    the

    sovereign

    decision

    is

    the realization

    of

    the

    ambi-

    guity

    of the distinction

    between

    bare and

    political

    life. It

    is

    law

    (political

    ife)

    that

    s

    not

    law

    (insofar

    as

    it

    steps

    outside

    of the

    strictures

    and limitations

    of formal

    law)

    dealing

    with bare

    ife

    (that

    s,

    nonpolitical

    ife),

    and

    insofar

    as

    it does

    so that

    nonpolitical

    bare)

    life

    it

    treats s

    political.

    The

    result is the

    paradox

    of

    a sacrifice that

    is

    dedicated

    to

    no

    legal

    or

    religious

    end

    [114]

    but that

    participates

    n and

    affirms

    the

    economy

    or

    logic

    of

    the

    legal/religious system

    as a

    metaphysical,

    political system.

    Where

    in

    Ren6

    Girard's

    superficially

    similar account of

    sacrifice the victim is a

    scapegoat

    for

    the

    murderous

    desires of

    the

    community

    hat

    unites

    around

    her,

    here the stakesare

    considerablyhigher.

    Instead of an act of self-protectionon the partof the community[Girard4, 101-02],

    sacrifice

    is the

    performance

    of the

    metaphysical

    assertion

    of

    the

    human:

    he

    Jew,

    the

    Gypsy,

    and

    the

    gay

    man die that

    the

    German

    may

    affirm

    his

    transcendence

    f his

    bodily,

    animal

    ife.22

    22.

    Agamben,

    I

    think,

    complicates

    his

    account

    unnecessarily

    when he concludes that the

    killing

    of

    bare

    life

    does

    not

    constitute

    a

    sacrifice

    [114]:

    the

    point

    is that the term

    "sacrifice"

    is

    here understood

    n a

    different

    way,

    as

    a

    move in a

    different

    and more

    undamental

    economy,

    one

    that

    produces

    a transcendence nstead

    of

    observing

    one.

    That

    said,

    Agamben'sanalysis

    here owes

    a great deal to Bataille'sseminalessay, "Hegel,Death and Sacrifice," one of the two Bataille

    textscited

    in his

    bibliography,

    hough

    only briefly

    referred

    o

    in his text.

    In

    this

    readingofAlexander

    Kojeve's

    reading of Hegel,

    Bataille

    argues

    that the

    logic of

    the

    human

    practice

    of sacrifice

    is

    revealed

    in

    the

    Hegelian

    account

    of

    the role

    of

    death in the constitution

    of

    the human.

    "Death

    alone assures

    the existence

    of

    a

    'spiritual'

    or

    'dialectical'

    being....

    If

    the animal which consti-

    tutes man

    s

    natural

    being

    did

    not

    die,

    and-what

    is

    more-if

    death did

    not

    dwell in him

    as

    the

    source

    of

    his

    anguish-all

    the more so in that he

    seeks

    it

    out,

    desires it and sometimes

    reely

    chooses it-there

    would be no man

    or

    liberty,

    no

    history

    or

    individual.

    n

    other

    words,

    if

    he revels

    in what nevertheless

    rightens

    him,

    if

    he is the

    being,

    identical

    with

    himself

    who

    risks

    (identical)

    being

    itself

    then

    man

    is

    truly

    a

    Man: he

    separates himselffrom

    the animal." The

    simple

    extinc-

    diacritics /

    winter 2000

    47

    This content downloaded from 192.43.227.18 on Tue, 17 Jun 2014 02:46:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Agmben Dead

    12/22

    .::x

    :aA:

    .. ...

    .. ..

    ........

    .

    .'m

    f.?

    This content downloaded from 192.43.227.18 on Tue, 17 Jun 2014 02:46:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Agmben Dead

    13/22

    Contemporary

    nstances of this threshold ife

    abound,

    rom

    refugees

    and

    people

    in

    concentration

    amps

    to

    "neomorts"

    nd

    figures

    in "overcomas"whom we are

    tempted

    to turn

    nto

    organ

    farms.

    Perhaps

    he clearest

    example

    is that of

    people

    in

    camps

    forc-

    ibly

    subjected

    to extreme

    medical

    tests and

    prisoners

    who have been condemned to

    death who are

    asked to

    "volunteer"

    or the same:

    The

    particular

    status

    of

    the VPs

    [Versuchspersonen]

    was decisive:

    they

    were

    persons

    sentenced to

    death

    or

    detained

    in a

    camp,

    the

    entry

    into which meant

    the

    definitive

    exclusion

    rom

    the

    political

    community.Precisely

    because

    they

    were

    lacking

    almost

    all the

    rights

    and

    expectations

    hat we

    characteristically

    attribute

    to

    human

    existence,

    and

    yet

    were still

    biologically

    alive

    [biologicamente

    ancora

    vita],

    they

    came

    to

    be

    situated

    at a limit

    zone

    [una

    zona-limite]

    between

    ife

    and

    death,

    inside and

    outside,

    in

    which

    they

    were

    no

    longer anything

    but bare

    life

    [nuda vita].

    Those

    who are sentenced to death

    and those who dweltincampsare thus in someway unconsciouslyassimilated

    to

    homines

    sacres,

    to a

    life

    that

    may

    be

    killed without

    he

    commission

    of

    homi-

    cide. Like

    the

    fence

    of

    the

    camp,

    the interval between death sentence and ex-

    tion

    of

    the

    life of

    the animal

    body

    alone is

    not

    sufficient.

    As in

    Agamben's

    reading of

    Aristotle,

    language

    too is

    necessary.

    On Bataille's account

    this is

    because

    "language

    .. alone

    founds

    the

    separation of

    elements and

    by founding

    it

    founds itself

    on

    it,

    within a world

    of separated

    and

    denominatedentities."

    The death

    of

    the animal

    life

    that

    is

    required or

    the

    emergence of

    the

    human

    being

    is a death that no

    purely

    animal

    life

    could ever die. The

    animal,

    on

    Bataille's ac-

    count,

    is lost

    in the sea

    of life. If

    it

    ceases

    to

    live,

    it

    is

    replacedby

    another

    of

    its

    kind,

    another

    that

    does not differ essentially rom it. In effect, it remainspresent. "Theonly true death supposes

    separation

    and,

    through

    he

    discourse which

    separates,

    the consciousness

    of being separated."

    Hence,

    if

    death

    is

    required

    n order

    or

    the

    human

    being

    to

    separate

    itselffrom

    its animal

    being,

    to some

    extent

    that

    separation

    must

    already

    have taken

    place

    in

    language.

    Death

    is

    not

    truly

    death-that

    is,

    it is not or

    does not allow

    for

    the

    metaphysical

    overcoming

    of

    the

    animal-unless

    it

    is

    the death

    of

    a human

    being.

    (It

    is in

    this context that Bataille cites

    Kojeve

    s

    "bizarre"

    and

    perfectly apt

    saying,

    that

    man is

    "'the

    anthropomorphic nimal.'")

    The

    circularity

    here is

    pre-

    cisely

    that

    ofAgamben

    s

    bare

    life:

    bare

    life

    is what is not

    political,

    whatthe

    political

    life

    exuviates:

    and

    yet for

    it to

    perform

    this

    function

    it must in some sense be

    political

    already.

    Bataille is

    well

    aware

    of

    the

    paradoxes

    this entails:

    "In

    theory,

    t is his

    natural,

    animal

    being

    whose

    death

    re-

    veals Man to himself but the revelationnever takesplace. For when the animalbeing supporting

    him

    dies,

    the

    human

    being himself

    ceases to

    be.

    In

    order

    or

    Man

    to

    reveal

    himself ultimately

    o

    himself

    he would have

    to

    die,

    but he would have to do it while

    living-watching

    himself ceasing

    to be

    "

    [Bataille

    12,

    15-16,

    19-20].

    For Bataille

    if

    not

    or Hegel,

    the

    solution

    to this is

    sacrifice

    and "the

    necessity

    of

    spectacle

    ":

    the

    explanation

    or

    the almost

    universal

    practice

    of sacrifice

    is

    that human

    beings

    do in

    fact

    need

    to

    undergo

    this

    sublation;

    and their

    solution

    to the above

    paradox

    is to

    kill

    an animal

    whose

    physical

    life

    stands in

    for

    their own.

    If

    we

    disregard

    Bataille's

    emphasis upon

    religious

    ritual t is clear that he is

    describing

    the same

    Aufhebung

    hat

    Agamben

    attributes

    o Aristotle-the

    difference

    being

    that

    Hegel

    and Bataille

    's

    references

    o death

    explic-

    itly

    commit them

    to

    a

    process

    that

    endangers

    and

    rejects

    bare

    life.

    Why

    hen

    doesn't

    Agamben

    discuss

    the Bataille

    article-why

    turn o Aristotle

    nstead?

    In his

    ew

    commentson Bataille in this

    book,he

    suggests

    thatBataille's

    analysis

    of sovereignty

    s

    compromised y

    its insistence

    upon

    the

    erotic nature

    of sacrifice

    [113]

    and

    by

    its

    too-ready acceptance of

    the

    early

    twentieth-century

    anthropologicalreadingof

    the sacred

    [75].

    One

    result

    of

    this

    is that Bataille is not able to think

    out the

    specifically political

    nature

    of

    the

    logic

    of

    sacrifice

    he uncovers. To

    ocate the

    genesis of

    that

    logic

    in Aristotle's Politics would make

    good

    this

    lack. This

    is

    something

    that Bataille is

    unable

    to do in

    part

    because he assumes that the

    logic of sacrifice

    and death is alien to Greek

    philosophy

    as a whole:

    "for

    Hegel,

    the human

    reality

    which he

    places

    at the

    heart,

    and

    center

    of

    the

    totality

    s

    very

    different rom

    that

    of

    Greek

    philosophy.

    His

    anthropology

    s that

    of

    the Judeo-

    Christiantradition"

    [12],

    for

    which

    the

    figure

    of

    Christ

    on the cross serves as the model

    of

    all

    transcendence

    of

    the bestial.

    diacritics

    /

    winter 2000

    49

    This content downloaded from 192.43.227.18 on Tue, 17 Jun 2014 02:46:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Agmben Dead

    14/22

    ecution delimits an

    extratemporal

    and

    extraterritorial

    hreshold

    [soglia]

    in

    which the human

    body

    is

    separated rom

    its normal

    [normale]

    political

    status

    and

    abandoned,

    in a

    state

    of

    exception

    [in

    stato

    di

    eccezione],

    to

    the most

    extreme

    misfortunes.

    159]

    When,in the UnitedStates,mencondemned o deathhave beenoffered the possibility

    of

    parole

    in

    exchange

    for

    "volunteering"

    o

    undergo

    tests

    that

    could not be

    imposed

    upon

    those with

    full

    rights

    of

    citizenship

    [156-57],

    the

    reasoning

    was

    quite

    understand-

    able,

    and

    even attractive n

    its

    economy

    and

    "fairness":

    iven

    that

    the

    person

    has been

    condemned

    o

    die,

    he has

    essentially

    already

    ost his life. As

    far as the law is concerned

    his

    life is no

    longer

    his

    own,

    and

    in

    that

    sense he is a

    "living

    dead man"

    [131].

    Hence

    therewill be no crime

    against

    him if his

    life is "lost"

    again.

    But neitherwill

    that

    deathbe

    the

    imposition

    of

    the

    death

    penalty.

    ndeed,

    t

    is

    precisely

    insofaras he

    awaits execution

    that

    he

    remains alive:

    his

    life remains

    only

    to be

    taken

    from him in the

    moment

    of

    punishment.Death ntheexperimenthusrevealstheparadoxesof deathrowasasphere

    that

    delayed

    penalty

    makes

    possible,

    that

    of

    the thresholdbetween life and

    death.23

    When the

    threshold

    of

    death row holds more than one or

    two

    victims,

    the result

    s

    the

    camp.

    Historically

    developing

    out

    of martial

    aw,

    it

    is

    itself an included exclusion

    from the

    penal

    system

    [20, 166-67].

    If

    the Aristotelian

    distinction

    between

    polis

    life

    and bare life with which we

    began

    was

    meantto

    secure and

    define the

    human,

    he

    total

    politicization

    of life

    that

    is

    the

    camp signals

    the

    collapse

    of

    this

    project.Agamben's

    characterization

    an be

    understood s

    an

    attempt

    o more

    systematically

    workout

    Arendt's

    paradoxical

    claim

    that

    "life

    in

    the concentration

    amps

    . .

    .

    stands outside

    of life and

    death"

    [Originsof

    Totalitarianism

    44].

    Here

    the

    exception

    becomes

    the

    norm-or,

    to

    be more

    precise,

    the distinctionbetweenthe two is

    wholly

    effaced. "The

    camp

    is the

    space

    [lo

    spazio]

    of

    this absolute

    mpossibility

    of

    deciding

    [decidere]

    between fact

    and

    law,

    rule and

    application,exception

    and

    rule,

    which nevertheless

    ncessantly

    decides

    [decide]

    between

    them"

    [173].

    In the name of

    the health

    of

    the

    body

    of

    the

    nation,

    n

    the

    attempt

    o

    produce

    a

    single

    and

    undivided

    people

    [179],

    and in

    response

    to the decision

    of

    the

    Fiihrer,

    whose own

    body

    has

    itself

    become one with the law

    [184],

    the

    nation

    takes

    on the endless

    task

    of

    its

    self-delineation;

    hat

    is,

    it moves into the threshold hat

    defines

    it,

    a threshold hat has

    awaited

    t since

    Aristotle'sPolitics.

    23.

    Agamben

    does not mention

    Antigone,

    but his discussion

    of

    the

    symbiosis

    of

    sovereignty

    and

    sacred

    life

    is

    surely

    reminiscent

    of

    this most

    political

    of

    tragedies.

    The action

    of

    the

    play

    revolvesarounda

    conflict

    over the

    city's

    duties

    towarda

    body

    that s

    placed

    neither