a fri philosophy

Upload: ademario-ashanti

Post on 04-Jun-2018

220 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/14/2019 A Fri Philosophy

    1/18

  • 8/14/2019 A Fri Philosophy

    2/18

  • 8/14/2019 A Fri Philosophy

    3/18

    57

    Phronimon Volume 13(2) 2012

    influence and mutual enrichment that take place in the relationship between human beings,

    and between them and their world, is dialogic in a broader and deeper sense. Dialogue in such

    a broad sense is a very pivotal plank in the relations of humans with themselves and with the

    world, and in their quest for collective synergy towards the improvement of life in general.

    Paulo Freire says that dialogue is the encounter between men, mediated by the world, in

    order to name the world (cf Smith 2001).

    Viewed from this broad perspective, dialogue according to Burbules is a kind of social

    relationship that engages its participants (Burbules 1993: 19). On account of this engagement,

    certain conditions are necessary for its fruitful evolution. The physicist David Bohm names

    three of these. First, those involved must suspend their assumptions. Second, they must vieweach other as colleagues or peers, and then there must be a facilitator to hold the context of

    dialogue (Bohm 2012). It is clear from this that Bohm is concentrating more on the technical

    process of dialoguing in a set situation and for determined ends that he has worked so hard to

    foster. Burbules (1993: 36-46) discourses other conditions which he calls the virtues or

    emotions of dialogue and they include concern, trust, respect, appreciation, affection and

    hope.

    In line with the virtues and emotions of dialogue as discussed by Burbules (1993), we

    can outline the following as necessary conditions for genuine and fruitful dialogue. In the first

    place there must be recognition of the humanity of the human agents in the dialogic situation.

    The necessity for this recognition is axed on the realisation that without it the give and take

    process that is an essential result of dialogue is truncated. Recognition of humanity entails

    certain equality as humans, since fruitful dialogue is atrophied once one party assumes the

    position of superiority or inferiority. With a sense of humanity and equality, there arises respect

    for the other persons, for the context of their lives and the world within which and with which

    dialogue must take place. These requirements then make possible openness to the views of

    the other. In this regard, Plato and Socratic dialogues may not be the best examples of

    dialogues since in them Socrates invariably ends up as the victor in the verbal conversation

    that is very often structured in such a way as to exhibit how untenable or impracticable the

    opposing views are. But respect for and openness to the views of the other does not preclude

  • 8/14/2019 A Fri Philosophy

    4/18

  • 8/14/2019 A Fri Philosophy

    5/18

    59

    Phronimon Volume 13(2) 2012

    Hail, thou Flame, which comest and goest, I have not spoken lies

    Hail, Crushe of bones, who comest forth from Suten-henen, I have not snatched away food

    Hail, thou who shootest forth the Flame, who comest forth from Het-Ptah-ka, I have not caused

    pain.

    Hail, thou who comest from Amentet, I have not committed fornicatio (Hord & Lee 1995: 21).

    The dialogic intent of the declaration is seen in its effort to convince the celestial audience of

    the standard of morality which the declarant has tried to live by. In a sense it is an appeal to

    the divinity to fulfil its part of the bargain since the human agent has, in his own assertion,

    fulfilled his own part. The awaited reaction is admittance of Ani, the innocent, into the abode of

    the righteous. But in a real sense the declaration is addressed to living human beings. In

    outlining different aspects of social morality, Maat, it is both an argument and an affirmation.

    The declaration argues about the authenticity of these ethical standards and underlies the

    necessity of embracing them for the fulfilment of the demands of Maat. As argumentation and

    affirmation, it is to be expected that in the real context of the declaration, the human audience

    is also expected to elicit a reaction, perhaps a presentation of an opposed view or

    acquiescence with the standard announced. Thus the declaration becomes just one side of a

    dialogue comprehensively viewed has many parts. It is clear that in this case the other side is

    not expressed and needs some interpretation before being made more explicit.

    While dialogic and dialectical implications could be read in other genres, it is in the

    dialogues of Plato that the literary philosophic style assumes a prominent place in Western

    philosophy. Gilbert Ryle (1967: 315) asserts that the usual way of publishing compositions

    be they verses or prose was oral delivery, and thus the dialogues of Plato, like others of its

    kind, were also meant to be recited to the public by the author. The dialogues were therefore

    dramatic in form and were meant to be recited to a drama-loving audience. That explains why

    dialogues had to be short in order to capture and retain the attention of the audience. Thus

    only the Republic and the uncompleted Laws were the exception and must have been

    intended for special academic audience that would reassemble many times to follow up the

    conversation. Through Platos dialogue the discussions of Socrates with his Athenian

  • 8/14/2019 A Fri Philosophy

    6/18

    60

    Phronimon Volume 13(2) 2012

    interlocutors are outlined. In the opinion of Francoise Armengaud (1989: 364), through these

    dialogues philosophy attains its plenitude and also manifests for the first time its creative-

    destructive power. Thus the Socratic dialogue traces what for Armengaud is the essence of

    philosophy, the shared research where the master forms the students and is at the same time

    formed by them. Therefore, philosophic dialogue is really dialectical, generated by necessity

    and movement and aimed at being and plenitude.

    The presentation of philosophic reflections in the form of dialogue was also a strong

    trade mark of the Roman writer Cicero, whose De amititia (On Friendship) and the Tusculan

    Disputationsover the question of death and immortality were presented in dialogic forms. Also

    in the medieval times, scholastic philosophy tried to imitate the dialectical form of philosophicdialogue. Its dialogic method starts by identifying the question for discussion and stating to the

    full the points opposed to the conviction the author was going to argue for, and then stating a

    sed contra, which is usually a statement that puts into question the major objection of the

    supposed opponent. It then goes on to outline as many points as possible against the

    opposing view before taking a final position. For Armengaud, scholastic dialogue is not a

    shared research and concern but a rhetorical form of intellectual dogmatism (une forme

    rhethorique de la dogmatique intellectuele) (Armengaud 1989: 364). It is important to note the

    dialogic character of scholasticism that first recognised the presence of contrary and opposing

    views, and was able to develop a method that afforded the possibility of listening and taking

    due consideration of the opponents views.

    It remains true, however, that the strict structuring of dialogue procedure among the

    scholastics aided what Armengaud calls intellectual dogmatism. This is evident in the disputes

    between the Franciscan and Dominican scholars at the University of Paris, for example, in

    which there is a surprising consistency among lines of scholars determined strictly by whether

    they were Franciscan or Dominican. For Armengaud though, scholastic dogmatism is believed

    to have strongly influenced subsequent dialogues in the history of Western philosophy. Among

    them Nicholas Malebranches Entretiens sur la metaphysique et la religion (1688); Bishop

    Berkeleys Two Dialogues between Hylas and Philonus (1713); as well as Denis Diderots Le

    reve de dAlembert(1769). JG. Fichtes The Destination of man; SpinozasShort treatise; as

  • 8/14/2019 A Fri Philosophy

    7/18

    61

    Phronimon Volume 13(2) 2012

    well as Aelread of Rivaulxs Spiritual friendshipare among the works that tried to imitate the

    written conversational model of presentation (Armengaud 1989).

    Also of major importance is the tradition of philosophic correspondence in the modern

    period of Western philosophy. Its importance is axed on the increased openness of the

    interlocutors in these letters much more than in the written works of the authors. Some of the

    famous correspondences include that of Descartes with Princess Elizabeth; the

    correspondence of Spinoza; Malebranches correspondence with JJ Dortous de Mairan on the

    doctrines of Spinoza; and the correspondence on liberty between Leibniz and Arnauld.

    Another form of dialogue in the art of philosophising is debate on important issues in

    philosophy. One remembers the famous debate between Frederick Copleston and BertrandRussell on the existence of God (1948), and between AJ Ayer and Frederick Copleston on

    logical positivism (1949). These forms of verbalised dialogue have certainly marked the history

    of philosophy in a special manner. But there are aspects of dialogic interaction not spoken in

    the form of words. Philosophys engagement with its context, with the problems of ethics, with

    the socio-economy, and politics of its time, is a way of bringing the principles of its reflection to

    an encounter with its actual context. Philosophical hermeneutics brings this aspect of the

    philosophic engagement to the foremost level. It zeroes into the historical, cultural,

    educational, religious and more background of the society and the individual philosopher. The

    relationship which exists between these non-philosophical raw-materials or symbols of

    reflection and the outcome of individual reflection is the foundation on which philosophy is

    actually based (Okere 1983). Real and relevant philosophising must at the end of the day be

    in some very real way hermeneutical. Two examples elucidate this assertion: the quest for

    identity in much of contemporary African philosophy, and the results of John Rawls (1971) in

    his famous book,A theory of justice.

    The issue of identity is a central issue in much of contemporary African philosophy. The

    main reason behind the emergence of the question of identity is the historical racism of the

    European society against Africans and the creation of Africa in Western libraries (Mudimbe

    1988). This attitude finds most prominent expression among the philosophers of the

    Enlightenment. It is oblique in some, and open in others like David Hume, Immanuel Kant and

  • 8/14/2019 A Fri Philosophy

    8/18

    62

    Phronimon Volume 13(2) 2012

    Michelle de Montesquieu, but it was a much generalised sentiment underlying the whole of the

    colonial enterprise. The fall-out of this on the psyche of contemporary African philosophic

    thinkers is the issue of identity, that of who and what we are. On the positive note it is sort of

    unconscious self-assertion in the face of a barrage of historical denigration. On the negative

    side, its strangle hold gives rise to what Kwasi Wiredu (1985: 222) describes as the fallacy of

    uniqueness, which is the supposition that for Africans to have an authentic identity, they need

    to be unique in their social and political forms and in many other things besides.

    The book of John Rawls,A theory of justice,is another example of the way in which the

    context can strongly influence if not predetermine the outcome of philosophic reflections. There

    is no gainsaying that justice is always a central issue in human communal existence. It is infact the reason for the existence of social and political institutions, and thus for Augustine

    (1952), a human community turns into a band of robbers once justice is removed from its

    operations. Still, be justice as general and as fundamental as it wants, Rawlss theory has as

    its fulcrum the liberal Western society. That is why in spite of the ingeniously crafted original

    position and the veil of ignorance, what comes out in the form of his two principles of justice, is

    very much biased in favour of the liberal society where the freedom of the individual is the

    most basic desideratum. It is interesting to remark that under Rawlss background, the groups

    quest for identity can hardly arise. These examples indicate that hermeneutics which take

    account of the total life experience and circumstances that surround the results of human

    thinking is like a palimpsest that underlies much of the results of philosophic engagement,

    irrespective of the tradition in question. This act of proper weighing, this taking into account of

    the total influence on philosophy is in a very deep sense dialogical, since dialogue as we have

    seen is much broader than mere verbal conversation but includes total reflexive interaction

    with the agents humanity, that of his interlocutors and the total context of his philosophising.

    4. ANCIENT GREEK PHILOSOPHY IN DIALOGUE WITH AFRICAN PHILOSOPHY

    From the above viewpoint, Greek philosophy and African philosophy have been in deep

    dialogue since antiquity. More specifically, Ionian philosophy and ancient Egyptian philosophic

  • 8/14/2019 A Fri Philosophy

    9/18

    63

    Phronimon Volume 13(2) 2012

    traditions were in mutual interaction and influence with each other. We do not need to be

    distracted by the debate over the colour of ancient Greek thinkers or the different ethnic groups

    that built up the Egyptian civilization. Suffice it to note that modern researches, especially by

    Egyptologists, have unfolded the philosophical profundity of this ancient culture. The

    philosophical patrimony of Egyptian civilization has been documented by such researchers as

    M Bilolo, Theophile Obenga, JP Allen, and JH Breasted. It is possible that the reception of

    these works has been prejudiced by such titles as Onyewuenyis African origin of Greek

    philosophy (1993) which is in turn a milder form of George G James title, Stolen legacy

    (1992). Our point here is that ancient Egypt at its zenith scratched the limits of both civilization

    and philosophy within its epoch. On the philosophic terrain, for instance, a passage from thePapyrus of Leiden I 350 on the nature of the divinity contains the following statement:

    Secret of development but glittering of forms,

    Wonderful god of many developments,

    All gods boast in him,

    In order to magnify themselves in his perfection, like his divinity.

    ..

    No god knows his appearance,

    No processional image of him is unfolded through inscription,

    No one testifies to him accurately.

    He is too secret to uncover his awesomeness,

    He is too great to investigate, too powerful to know.

    Instantaneously falling face to face into death

    Is for the one who expresses his secret identity, unknowingly or knowingly.

    There is no god who knows how to invoke him with it.

    Manifest God whose identity is hidden, inasmuch as it is inaccessible.

    JP Allen (1988: 53) describes this passage as perhaps the clearest surviving expression of

    the Egyptian concepts of immanent and transcendent divinity, and of the acceptance of both in

    Egyptian thought. The first sentence of the passage expresses the presence of the two

  • 8/14/2019 A Fri Philosophy

    10/18

    64

    Phronimon Volume 13(2) 2012

    opposed attributes, describing the divinity as secret of development but glittering of form. In a

    similar style, the closing line describes it as a being that is both manifest and has hidden

    identity. Here we see what the scholastics will much later call Concordia oppositorum, and it is

    interesting to see how much Thales of Miletus with his simple assertion that all is water, pales

    before such level of philosophic reflection.

    The relationship between ancient Greek and ancient Egyptian philosophy is seen clearly

    in the acknowledgement of Aristotle in his Metaphysicsof the Egyptian origin of mathematical

    arts on account of the leisure of its priests. This acknowledgement is like a harbinger of more

    doctrinal connection between the two ancient philosophical traditions. In an article published by

    the eminent Egyptologist James Henry Breasted, more than one century ago, there is athorough study of what he described as the oldest known formulation of a philosophical

    Weltanschauung (Breasted 1901: 39). Titled The philosophy of a Memphite priest, the study

    highlights the role of the Egyptian deity Ptah as inscribed in an old and badly damaged ancient

    Egyptian stone. The kernel of the finding is that the inscription presents a philosophical

    understanding of the function of Ptah as the mind and speech of the Gods (Breasted 1901:

    46). The priestly thinker chants of Ptah as the source of the power by which heart and tongue

    carry out the plans and ideas which he furnishes (Breasted 1901: 48). Ptah both suggests

    every plan and idea and at the same time furnishes the power of its execution. He is the divine

    source of all things:

    Everything comes forth form him, whether offering, or food, or divine oblation, or any

    good thing . Since he formed the gods in their adyta, he made the towns, he equipped

    the nomes, he placed the gods in the adyta, he made their offerings flourish, he

    equipped their adyta, he made the likeness of their bodies to the satisfaction of their

    hearts (Breasted 1901: 48).

    In spite of the paradoxes involved in Ptahs creation of the gods, Breasted presents a clear

    picture of the philosophy of the Memphite priest in terms very close to Greek concepts of nous

    and logos. Assuming the existence of matter, it affirms that all things first existed in the mind.

  • 8/14/2019 A Fri Philosophy

    11/18

    65

    Phronimon Volume 13(2) 2012

    Speech or tongue is the channel through which they translate into objective reality. In the

    ensuing world, the thought impulses of all living creatures are owed to the same mind that

    created them. The outcome of their thought is therefore primarily due to the all pervasive

    mind, and only in a secondary manner to the creatures in question. Their work is therefore a

    further affirmation of the statement that all things exist first in the mind of the god (Breasted

    1901: 51). Breasteds study of the ancient Egyptian inscription arrives at the following

    conclusions:

    First: that the early Egyptian did much more and much better thinking on abstract

    subjects than we have hitherto believed, having formed a philosophical conception of theworld of men and things, of which no people need be ashamed. Second: it is obvious

    that the above conception of the world forms quite a sufficient basis for suggesting the

    later notions of nous and logos hitherto supposed to have been introduced into Egypt

    from abroad at a much later date. Thus the Greek tradition of the origin of their

    philosophy in Egypt undoubtedly contains more of truth than has in recent years been

    conceded (Breasted 1901: 54).

    These conclusions pinpoint the acknowledgment of ancient Greek thinkers of Egypt as thesource of their philosophy, but the study went on to prove by a deep archaeology of the

    concept of logos that in fact it originated from ancient Egypt. JP Allen reached the same

    conclusion and referred to Breasteds study in a book Genesis in Egypt(Allen 1988). What is

    important for our purpose is that there was clear traffic between the two regions and that the

    philosophical minds were in dialogue, leading to mutual influence. From the inscription of the

    Memphite priest this influence appears to have had more impact on later development of

    Greek philosophy but it is reasonable that following the natural order of things, there could

    have been some mutuality of influence even at this early time.

  • 8/14/2019 A Fri Philosophy

    12/18

    66

    Phronimon Volume 13(2) 2012

    5. AFRICAN PHILOSOPHY: FERTILE TERRAIN FOR GREEK PHILOSOPHICAL

    INFLUENCE

    The interface between Greek and African philosophy experienced a boost with North African

    patristic thinkers. These include Clement of Alexandria, Origen, Lactantius, Cyprian of

    Carthage, and so forth. But by far the greatest among them, and also the greatest non-biblical

    theologian of the Christian world, was Aurelius Augustine of Hippo. Augustines philosophy and

    theology were suffused by the structure of Platos philosophy. Augustine is widely known to

    have Christianised Plato mainly by making use of the pivotal role of the transcendence in the

    explanation of being and its varied operations in terrestrial existence. Augustines philosophy isthus a thinly veiled dialectic of Platos theory of Ideas. After a tour of all the available

    philosophical schemes of his time in the City of God (Augustine 1958: 150), Augustine

    proclaimed Plato most suitable for the interpretation and understanding of Christianity. One

    obvious idea that is endemically Platonic is the conviction that the material and worldly are

    always of lower value than the transcendent and immaterial, which are the archetypical origin

    and explanation of the material, its susceptibility to change and inconstancy as well as its

    inability to be a lasting explanation for accepted standards and values. Thus in general the

    material or the worldly is always lower than the transcendent and the other worldly. For Plato

    the other worldly is encapsulated in the world of Ideasand ultimately in the Idea of the good,

    while for Augustine, the heavenly, God himself becomes in some way the real value of the

    mundane and the changeable.

    A clear illustration of this thought structure is Augustines thought on Friendship in the

    Confessions (Augustine 1952). Augustine praises friendship almost in hyperboles and is

    known to have tried on several occasions to form a community of friends in order to enjoy the

    full advantages of friendship relationship. In book 4 of the Confessions (4:8), Augustine

    recounts the different acts that show the joy of a friendship relationship: talking, laughing,

    giving and receiving kindness, reading good books, disagreeing as one with himself, teaching

    and learning from one another, missing the absent and welcoming them on their return:

  • 8/14/2019 A Fri Philosophy

    13/18

    67

    Phronimon Volume 13(2) 2012

    these and such-like things proceeding from our hearts as we give affection and

    receive it back, and shown by face, by voice, by the eyes, and a thousand other pleasing

    ways, kindled a flame which fused our very souls and of many made us one (Augustine

    1952: 4:8).

    Yet this moving experience of friendship does not grant it any lasting value in the Neoplatonic

    scheme of Augustine. He goes on in the next section to recount the pain felt at the death of a

    friend which makes the living friend to feel as though he himself were dead. Augustine then

    zeroes in on the transcendent friendship: blessed is the man that loves Thee, O God, and

    his friend in Thee, and his enemy for Thee. For he alone loses no one that is dear to him

    (Augustine 1952: 4:9). It means that, given the pains of the loss of a friend, the mundane

    friendship has no lasting value, but is rather like a pointer to the true friendship in God, in the

    same way that sensible realities point us to the world of forms in Plato.

    Still it is in the twentieth century, in what we can call the contemporary period in African

    philosophy, that we encounter even more overwhelming influence of ancient Greek philosophy.

    This came as a consequence of colonial history. Western academic philosophy reached most

    of Africa in the company of modern Western education after colonisation. The first departments

    of philosophy were established at the time new universities were built first in South Africa.

    They were built under the background of rejection and denigration of the context of their

    insertion. They were meant to serve Africans but also structured as instruments of assimilation

    into the Western culture, history, and civilization of the superior colonisers. The consequence

    of this policy was that the study of all branches of the arts and humanities meant European

    studies. When philosophy was introduced it came with the weight of this prejudice. The study

    of philosophy became the study of Western philosophy and so history of philosophy for

    instance, became synonymous with history of Western philosophy.In most of African philosophy departments and faculties, ancient philosophy is simply

    the study of ancient Greek philosophy, usually starting from Thales, and for several reasons

    this practice has come to stick. Being schooled in the different periods of Western philosophy,

    African historians of philosophy have now been unconsciously borrowing the standard

  • 8/14/2019 A Fri Philosophy

    14/18

    68

    Phronimon Volume 13(2) 2012

    periodization of the history of Western philosophy. Abanukas (2011) recent book, A history of

    African philosophy,has exactly four periods: ancient, medieval, modern and contemporary as

    though there is standard periodization which the history of every regional philosophy must

    follow. The implication is that philosophical studies turn to be veritable instruments for cultural

    alienation.

    There are two points to note about this development. Philosophic alienation generated

    the debate on the existence and nature of African philosophy in the late 1960s and 1970s. It

    was an almost inevitable debate since most of the participants are those schooled in

    programmes in which philosophy was taken to be so exotic that it started only in ancient

    Greece and developed further in the West. Hence to speak of African philosophy and in factany other regional philosophy was an aberration. While this not very useful debate (Oguejiofor

    2003: 484) was going on, and while since then a consensus of thinkers has come to accept

    African philosophy both in its normative and prescriptive senses, there has been virtually no

    serious reversal in the colonial philosophy curriculum in the Africa continent. It means that

    students of philosophy in much of Africa today still go through a curriculum in which ancient

    philosophy still means ancient Greek philosophy. Most of these on graduation remain

    completely ignorant of ancient Egyptian philosophy.

    The project of Afrocentrism has not succeeded in changing the alienating content of

    philosophical studies in Africa. In summary, the Afrocentric movement tried to prove that in fact

    ancient Greek philosophy owed its existence to a stolen legacy, to borrow the title of James

    (1992). Onyewuenyi (1993) followed James project in his African origin of Greek philosophy.

    Granted that these works contain a lot of polemics, their aim was to puncture the pride of the

    absolute origin of philosophy in ancient Greece. Still the polemical content of the works, as well

    as ingrained prejudice in Western philosophy, appears to have precluded favourable reception

    and in a sense appreciation of other more academic researches on ancient Egyptian

    philosophy such as those of Molefi Kete Asante, Theophile Obenga, M Bilolo and Jacob

    Carouthers. The thesis of Afrocentrists was given a boost by Martine Bernals controversial

    Black Athena. Bernal (1987) presents two models of Greek history, the Aryan and Ancient

    models. While the Aryan speaks of an invasion from the north and the resultant mixture of

  • 8/14/2019 A Fri Philosophy

    15/18

    69

    Phronimon Volume 13(2) 2012

    Indo-European speaking Hellenes and their indigenous subjects, the ancient model suggests

    ancient Egyptian dominance which civilized the native inhabitants, creating a channel for the

    influence of ancient Egyptian thought. The controversy attendant on Bernals Black Athena is

    more an indication of the strength of academic prejudice than any other factor. Bernals thesis

    and the reaction to it expose what can be called the colour of otherwise presumed neutrality of

    philosophic reflections. On this Bernal writes:

    If a Black were to say what I am now putting in my books, their reception would be very

    different. They would be assumed to be one-sided and partisan, pushing a Black

    Nationalist line, and therefore dismissed (cf Mudimbe 1988: 103)

    6. HISTORICAL AND PSYCHOLOGICAL CONSTRAINTS

    The attitude that Bernal describes in the above statement represents one of the strongest

    obstacles to fruitful dialogue between different traditions of philosophy. It is in one guise

    historical, but its historicity predates colonial denigration and consequent complexes generated

    both on the side of the colonised and colonisers. It can be traced back to the period of the

    Enlightenment. Its focal point is the erection of philosophy to the status of being the

    determinant of humanity. Tsenay Serequeberhan (1996: 3) points out that this was done

    without the benefit of an argument. Almost half a century ago, this assumption generated the

    debate on whether Africa had a philosophy or not. Precisely because it was based on

    uncritically accepted presuppositions, it neglected the historicity of African philosophy. Placides

    Tempels project was like a contradiction of this assumption which somehow tailored the

    development of contemporary African philosophy. For Tempels (1948: 15), the importance of

    Bantu philosophy lies in the fact that if the so called primitive people had no system of thought(philosophy), they would not be human (Celui quie pretend que les primitifs ne possedent point

    de systeme de pensee, les rejette doffice de la class des home). This is also the point of

    debate on the existence of African philosophy. In the whole of contemporary African

    philosophy, there is hardly any serious questioning of this latent assumption. What instead was

  • 8/14/2019 A Fri Philosophy

    16/18

    70

    Phronimon Volume 13(2) 2012

    generated was the effort to give the lie to the assumption by proving the existence of African

    philosophy. In some way this is an unconscious or surreptitious reaction, since the events of

    history had already created what Nyasanyi calls superiority in inferiority. Thus the effort of

    African thinkers who opposed the existence of African philosophy was equally exerted in the

    name of philosophy in the real sense as opposed to the debased sense (Oruka 1975: 45) as

    though philosophers have ever agreed on the definition and nature of their engagement.

    But the debate itself is meta-philosophical. Objectively speaking it called attention to the

    almost chimeric nature of a discipline in which, for instance, Nicholo Machiavelli and Thomas

    Hobbes are graded on the same pedestal; a discipline in which GW Hegel is foisted into the

    hall of fame even though his knowledge of Greek philosophy, of human nature and of history isvery minimal. Debate on the existence and nature of African philosophy could have been an

    opportunity for self-questioning by all traditions of philosophy. But this was not to be. Till today

    it is hardly surprising how little is known of African philosophy in Western departments of

    philosophy. In this regard, Western philosophy still remains covered by hallows of superiority

    and arrogance, thinly veiled in the guise of specialisation. It is the same thin veil that tends to

    influence philosophical interest in many parts of Africa and it represents a throwback to the

    colonial era when dialogue in the sense of engagement with total humanity of the other was

    not prominent in the philosophical terrain. It is why some philosophy workers still think it is

    possible to live and work in Africa and have almost nothing to do with the African philosophic

    community and the shared problems of the continent. The result of such philosophy will

    certainly not be meaningful or relevant to its context.

    7. CONCLUSION: THE WAY FORWARD

    The central point of our essay is that broadly understood dialogue is a pivotal feature of the

    philosophical engagement and that African and Greek philosophies have been in dialogue

    starting from the ancient times. The result of this dialogue is evident in the long history of

    mutual influence which is marked by the interplay of the basic features of philosophic dialogue,

    such as respect and openness. In contemporary times, the inroad of ancient Greek philosophy

  • 8/14/2019 A Fri Philosophy

    17/18

    71

    Phronimon Volume 13(2) 2012

    into the African cultural world through colonialism ensured that instead of being mutually

    enriching, the study of Greek philosophy in many ways turned to be one additional factor in

    African cultural alienation. The reaction to this historic legacy has been a spur to further

    creativity in the contemporary African philosophy. That the situation of philosophic alienation

    still remains a dominant feature of philosophy in the African continent, is a pointer to the

    ambivalence of the African cultural reality which is replicated in contemporary African

    philosophy. Given the reality of our fast globalising world, the legacy of the historic dialogue

    between Greek and African philosophy should be seen beyond the factor of intellectual

    colonialism in view of imbibing the best attitudes of mutually enriching dialogue freed from both

    superiority and inferiority complexes. It is in so far as the different regional philosophies areable to engage with one another in that manner that the much needed inter-cultural and

    philosophic dialogue will answer to the real needs of our contemporary world. It is a world in

    which such needs are no longer exclusive to specific people, cultures, countries or continents.

    The world which is gravitating very fast to a pan-human community is realising that most of its

    major dilemmas are now common to humanity as a whole. Genuine dialogue in philosophy is

    one of the most fruitful ways of confronting these dilemmas, and the long history of the

    relationship between African and Greek philosophy is a useful guide to this all important

    project.

    BIBLIOGRAPHY

    Abanuka, B. 2011.A history of African philosophy. Onitsha: Spiritan Publications.

    Allen, JP. 1988. Genesis in Egypt: The philosophy of ancient Egyptian creation account. New Haven:

    Yale Egyptological Seminar, New Haven.

    Armengaud, F. 1989. Dialogue. In Encyclopedia Universalis, vol. 7, Paris, pp. 363-366.Breasted, JH. 1901. The philosophy of a Memphite priest. Zeitschrift feur Aegyptologische Studien, 39:

    39-54.

    Augustine. 1958. City of God, transl GG Walsh. New York: Image Books.

    Augustine. 1952.The Confessions, transl EB Pusey. Chicago: William Benton, Chicago.

  • 8/14/2019 A Fri Philosophy

    18/18

    72

    Phronimon Volume 13(2) 2012

    Bernal, M. 1987. Black Athena: The Afroasiatic roots of classical civilization, vol. 1: The fabrication of

    ancient Greece 1785-1985, New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press.

    Bohm, D. On meaning, purpose and exploration in dialogue, www.david-

    bohm.net/dialogue_exploration.html (Accessed on 8/4/2012).

    Burbules, N. 1993.Dialogue in teaching. Theory and practice. New York: Teachers College Press.

    Gadamer, HG. 1979.Truth and method, London: Sheed & Ward.

    Hord, FL & Lee JS (eds). 1995.I am because we are: readings in Black philosophy, Amherst:

    University of Massachusetts Press.

    Isaacs, W. 1999.Dialogue: the art of thinking together. New York: Doubleday.

    James, G. 1992.Stolen legacy: Greek philosophy is stolen Egyptian philosophy. Trenton: First Africa

    World Press.

    Mudimbe, VY. 1988. The invention of Africa: Gnosis, philosophy and the order of knowledge .

    Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

    Oguejiofor, JO. 2003. Problems and prospects of a history of African philosophy.American Catholic

    Philosophical Quarterly77: 477-498.

    Okere, T. 1983.African philosophy: a historico-hermeneutical investigation into the conditions of its

    possibility,Lanham: University Press of America.

    Onyewuenyi, I. 1993,African origin of Greek philosophy:an exercise in Afrocentrism. Nsukka:

    University of Nigeria Press.

    Oruka, OH. 1975. Fundamental principles to the question of African philosophy. Vol IV, No. 2, Ife:

    Nigeria.

    Rawls, J. 1971.A theory of justice(transl 1975 & 1999). Harvard University Press.

    Ryle G. 1967. Plato. InThe encyclopedia of philosophy.Paul Edwards (ed). New York: Macmillan: 314

    -333.

    Serequeberhan, T. 1996.The hermeneutics of African philosophy: horizon and discourse. London:

    Routledge.

    Smith, MK. 2001. Dialogue and conversation. The encyclopedia of informal education.www.infed.org/biblio/b-dialog.htm (Accessed on 8/4/2012).

    Tempels, P. 1948.La philosophie bantoue,Paris: Presence Africaine.

    Wiredu, K. 1985. Problems in African self-identification in the contemporary world. In Alwin Diemer (ed),

    Africa and the problems of its identity. Frankfurt : Peter Lang: 213 -222.