22-24-1-pb

Upload: sandra-loewe

Post on 03-Jun-2018

218 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/12/2019 22-24-1-PB

    1/5

    Film-Philosophy1.1 1997

    Jay Raskin

    The Friction Over the Fiction of Nonfiction Movie

    Carl R. PlantingaRhetoric and Representation in Nonfiction Film

    Cambridge University Press, 1997

    In the current debate or struggle between postmodernist and cognitive (or 'post-

    theory') movie theory, Carl Plantinga's new book Rhetoric and Representation

    in Nonfiction Filmfits into the latter's Aristotelian modernist/rationalist camp.

    What is interesting, however, is the way Plantinga uses the postmodernisttheory of the non-objectivity of nonfiction film to discredit the postmodernist

    theory of a potentially progressive reflexive documentary cinema. Plantinga

    theorizes that if there is no objectivity, this idea cancels all the way through,

    and even reflexive documentaries are suspect constructions ungrounded in

    reality. Because of the interesting and skillful style of argument, both sides

    should enjoy it -- as well as cinema buffs, filmmakers, film students, and the

    passing civilian tourist.

    The book is neatly divided into two parts. In the first, Plantinga discusses

    what nonfiction films claim to represent. In the second part he develops

    categories for nonfiction films based on their rhetorical style. The last chapter

    both sums up his conclusions from these parts and expands them into the field

    of culture, with an interesting case study of an old American documentary

    television series called The Twentieth Century.

    As far as representation in nonfiction films goes, Plantinga brings forth

    Nicholas Wolterstorff's theory of 'projected worlds'. Among the things that

    artists do is project worlds or portray 'states of affairs'. In nonfiction films, the

    artist-producers are asserting that these states of affairs either are occurring or

    did occur in the real world. Through a series of 'cues' the audience is made

    aware of this assertion or claim about the material presented. The way that

    nonfiction movies cue audiences is similar to the process described by David

    Bordwell in his important work Narration in the Fiction Film. So for example,

  • 8/12/2019 22-24-1-PB

    2/5

    Film-Philosophy1.1 1997

    a handheld camera, high levels of background noise, and a certain non-

    professionalism on the part of the actors might cue the audience that the scene

    is to be taken as naturally occurring and not staged for the camera. External

    information, for example, press reports and posters, also help to cue theaudience to take the claim seriously that a certain set of events happens or

    happened.

    Of cause there are fuzzy or complex cases such as JFKwhere it is hard to

    know precisely how to take the cues. The moment where an enlargement of the

    Zapruder film which shows Kennedy's head moving backward after being shot

    seems to be a piece of non-fiction mixed into a film which we are cued largely

    to take as fiction, but a fiction close to historical reality. Plantinga admits that'in this postmodern age, such intermixtures have become increasingly common',

    but maintains that the distinction between fiction and nonfiction 'is not merely

    in your head, but in films and in the cultural and historical context in which

    they are produced and viewed' (20).

    Surprisingly, here on the issue of representation, Plantinga generally

    supports postmodernist claims of the constructiveness of nonfiction films. He

    notes:

    the history of staging in nonfiction shows that the set of features, or

    family resemblances, we associate with nonfiction film constantly receded and

    expanded, as practices gain and lose acceptance. In light of this, it is most

    fruitful to think of nonfiction not in terms of unchanging or universal intrinsic

    properties, but as a socially constructed category that is fluid and malleable; it

    changes with history. (37)

    Here, as one often finds, there is much that postmodernist and cognitivist

    theory actually agree upon. Because Plantinga feels, 'nonfiction films are not

    imitations or re-presentations, but constructed representations', he is able to put

    them into the category of rhetoric, which leads him into the second part of his

    book.

    Doing something similar to what David Bordwell did for fiction films,

    Plantinga argues for a division of nonfiction films into the 'authoritative',

    'reflexive', and 'poetic'. The authoritative uses a 'formal voice'. It assumes a

  • 8/12/2019 22-24-1-PB

    3/5

    Film-Philosophy1.1 1997

    position of superior knowledge and teaches or explains something about the

    world. The reflexive film uses an 'open voice'. It is satisfied to show or explore

    something in the world, and does not directly tell the audience precisely what to

    think about its subject matter. The poetic film is interested in producing certainclassically artistic effects. A variant of the poetic film, the 'avant garde' film,

    aims at producing these emotions from the style of the film itself, which is, in

    fact, the subject matter of the film.

    Again there is no particular technique or set of techniques that definitely

    distinguishes one type of film from another. For example, an authoritative film

    like John Ford's Battle of Midwayuses a multiplicity of narrational voices, a

    technique usually adopted by reflexive films, e.g., Jean-Luc Godard's Ici EtAlleur. So again, just as when distinguishing between fiction and nonfiction,

    there are only family resemblances making up the cues that allow us to index a

    film as fiction or nonfiction -- we can only index the difference between

    authoritative, reflexive, and poetic nonfiction films using family resemblances

    of cues. One could call this type of classification system a kind of 'fuzzy

    essentialism', which seems to be a moderate compromise between an

    Aristotelian objective absolute essentialism and a subjective relativist anti-

    essentialism. Plantinga argues that the rhetorical style of a nonfiction film

    cannot be related to any kind of progressiveness or honesty. He writes that

    'reflexive strategies do not guarantee honesty, integrity, or genuine self-

    revelation on the part of the filmmaker(s)' (218). Put simply, a reflexive film

    can be as phoney or dishonest as any other.

    Curiously, in his last chapter, Plantinga analyses the old Walter Cronkite

    narrated television series The Twentieth Century. The analysis shows that the

    program was pure ideology (in the narrowest Marxist sense) expressing only

    the views of the American Ruling Class and justifying American policies as if

    they were eternal commands from God. This analysis seems to run counter to

    his general thesis that no social or political implications flow from the

    rhetorical style of a film. This case seems to be evidence that a certain style of

    telling people what to think about cinematic material follows from a certain

    world-view.

  • 8/12/2019 22-24-1-PB

    4/5

    Film-Philosophy1.1 1997

    Sadly, instead of exploring this possible contradiction to his general thesis

    -- and in the weakest part of the book -- Plantinga defends the television series.

    He feels that it is somehow better than some unnamed alternative, which I took

    to be some kind of Stalinist subjectivism. In the end his argument boils down tothis: both communist and capitalist propaganda are subjective and one sided,

    but at least capitalist propaganda desires to be objective and honest. But from

    Plantinga's own description, the real purpose of the The Twentieth Centurywas

    to promote the picture of the United States and its military apparatus as strong,

    dynamic, and in control of the world, while at the same time the series

    producers pretended to be objective and disinterested. Plantinga admits that his

    own analysis of the series, 'adds more evidence to that claim that as concepts,absolute objectivity, fairness, impartiality cannot be instantiated, and that as

    practices, they may mask subtle biases . . .' (212) -- but Plantinga still calls for

    the retention of the concepts in a 'relative' way.

    In opposition to this, I would say that 'relative' objectivity, fairness, and

    impartiality is exactly what has been historically instantiated by the ruling

    bourgeoisie, and that as practices, they have served to mask 'extreme' real

    biases. Plantinga's call for the relative use of these concepts is support for the

    status quo, while a demand for the absolute instantiations of these principles

    would be the radical demand. The capitalist media today defines objectivity and

    impartiality as presenting the liberal and conservative views of the capitalist

    class. This 'relative' objectivity and impartiality works to marginalize and

    repress the views of other classes and groups in society. The demand for 'real'

    objectivity and impartiality is a demand that these other classes and groups take

    power through the media. At least I hope it is.

    Plantinga ends by pointing out the many contradictions in nonfiction

    films:

    a medium of truths and deceits, recording and manipulation, biases and

    balance, art and mechanical technique, rhetoric and straightforward

    information. Nonfiction films are complex representations with an infinite

    diversity of possible uses. Theirs is a rhetorical and pragmatic complexity that

  • 8/12/2019 22-24-1-PB

    5/5