reinhold niebuhr's christian realism/christian idealism

21
Reinhold Niebuhr's Christian Realism/Christian Idealism COLM MCKEOGFI The wicked at heart probably know something. WOODY ALLEN, Without Feathers The foregoing quip captures a realization that came to the young Reinhold Niebuhr in the 192os and that turned the liberal Christian pastor away from pacifism and toward a more realist ethic of politics. From then until his death in 1971, Niebuhr was to remain always a liberal Christian of real ist bent. He was a liberal Christian in his concentration on the law of love as the only absolute and in his rejection of Christian fundamentalism, bibli cal literalism, and the consequent clash with science. He was a political re alist, and rose to national prominence as such in the 1930S and 1940s, in his dismissal of pragmatic pacifism and his advocacy of American responsibil ity to use force in opposing the Nazi and Soviet threats to the world. He was famous particularly for his sharp attacks on those who failed to see the lim its on morality in politics. Yet this realism was but one strand of Niebuhr's dualist approach to politics, the other being his Christian idealism. It was disillusionment following World War I that had turned Niebuhr into a reluctant pacifist. Through the 192os, however, he worried about his motives and whether his professed pacifism was linked to American self- interest and a powerful nation's support of the status quo. He wondered whether he would be as good a pacifist if he belonged to an unsatisfied nation rather than to a satisfied one, and whether his pacifism was really anything more than the "pacifism of the beast whose maw is crammed." Much American pacifism of the time, he suggested, was "an ethical subli mation of an essentially selfish national position," for "it is always the ten dency of those who have to extol the virtues of peace and order."2 Niebuhr renounced his pacifism, and began to develop his political re alism, not in the face of the deteriorating international situation in the late 191

Upload: others

Post on 30-Nov-2021

2 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Reinhold Niebuhr's Christian Realism/ChristianIdealismCOLM MCKEOGFI

The wicked at heart probably know something.

WOODY ALLEN, Without Feathers

The foregoing quip captures a realization that came to the young Reinhold

Niebuhr in the 192os and that turned the liberal Christian pastor away

from pacifism and toward a more realist ethic of politics. From then until

his death in 1971, Niebuhr was to remain always a liberal Christian of real

ist bent. He was a liberal Christian in his concentration on the law oflove as

the only absolute and in his rejection of Christian fundamentalism, bibli

cal literalism, and the consequent clash with science. He was a political re

alist, and rose to national prominence as such in the 1930S and 1940s, in his

dismissal of pragmatic pacifism and his advocacy ofAmerican responsibil

ity to use force in opposing the Nazi and Soviet threats to the world. He was

famous particularly for his sharp attacks on those who failed to see the lim

its on morality in politics. Yet this realism was but one strand of Niebuhr's

dualist approach to politics, the other being his Christian idealism.

It was disillusionment following World War I that had turned Niebuhr

into a reluctant pacifist. Through the 192os, however, he worried about his

motives and whether his professed pacifism was linked to American self-

interest and a powerful nation's support of the status quo. He wondered

whether he would be as good a pacifist if he belonged to an unsatisfied

nation rather than to a satisfied one, and whether his pacifism was really

anything more than the "pacifism of the beast whose maw is crammed."

Much American pacifism of the time, he suggested, was "an ethical subli

mation of an essentially selfish national position," for "it is always the ten

dency of those who have to extol the virtues of peace and order."2

Niebuhr renounced his pacifism, and began to develop his political re

alism, not in the face of the deteriorating international situation in the late

191

192 COLM MCKIIOGH

1930s, but in response to the sufferings of the American working class dur

ing the Great Depression. It was the influence of Marxism on Niebuhr in

the late 1920S and early 1930S that led to his acceptance of the necessity of

using power and force in the cause ofjustice. Power, the Detroit-based pas

tor came to believe, is the core of politics. It is the first source of authority

in politics, domestic and international, and it is neither intrinsically evil

nor unambiguously good. It is rather the instrument ofboth good and evil:

"power cannot be evil of itself, unless life itself be regarded as evil. For life

is power. It is inherently dynamic. Even the purest `reason' is power. Ac

cording to the Christian faith, perfect power and goodness are united only

in God."3

Power is the necessary means to social change and to the achievement

of a more tolerable justice. Yet power comes in many forms and an imbal

ance in any of these results in injustice. The achievement of a more tolerable

degree ofjustice must come then through the balancing of power. The pri

mary check on the power of groups, classes, and nations will be the power

of other groups, classes, and nations. This need for a balance of power is

permanent because of the perennial possibility of some dominant power

and therefore the perennial threat of injustice. The necessity for a power-

based authority, means that full justice can never be attained. All societies

require an organization of power yet the center of power within any com

munity is always biased and never fully just. Acceptance of this must lead

to acceptance that, although political authority must try to be impartial, it

can never succeed.

Niebuhr's realist approach, developed in the context of the domestic

socioeconomic situation in the United States, was applied by him to inter

national relations in the 193os. The threat from Nazi Germany was one of

which Niebuhr, brought up in a German-speaking family in the Ameri

can Midwest, was acutely aware. In contact with German churches and

conscious of German anger over the Versailles Treaty, he was to warn, as

early as 1931, of the threat to peace from the "1-litler movement."1 In 1933,

with Hitler's accession to power, he appealed to the U.S. churches and gov

ernment to find ways of relief for German Jews.5 By 1934, he decided that

a "new war in Europe is only a matter of years."6 In the face of the Nazi

threat, Niebuhr criticized forcefully and influentially the dominant strain

of pacifism in the interwar United States. This was the pragmatic paci

fism of which Niebuhr himself had been an exponent and which remained

widespread among his fellow liberal Protestants. But in his critique ofpac

ifism, Niebuhr distinguished between two types of pacifism: the absolute

REINHOLD NIEEUHR'S CHRISTIAN REALISM/CHRISTIAN IDEALISM 193

pacifism of the Christian perfectionist and the pragmatic pacifism ofmany

liberals. It was only the latter that Niebuhr rejected. The former he ac

cepted and valued. Indeed, he never failed to pay tribute to the pacifism

that was witness to the Christian ideal of non-coercive love but that never

claimed to be a political strategy. In 1940, long after he had rejected his

own pacifism, he wrote that such pacifists were not fools to be tolerated but

witnesses to be heard: "We who allow ourselves to become engaged in war

need this testimony of the absolutist against us, lest we accept the warfare

of the world as normative, lest we become callous to the horror of war, and

lest we forget the ambiguity of our own actions and motives and the risk

we run of achieving no permanent good from this momentary anarchy in

which we are involved."7

Christian Idealism

Niebuhr's distinction between two types of pacifism, and his rejection of

only one of them, was of immense significance to the development of his

dualist approach. For the perfectionist strand of Niebuhr's approach shares

its roots with the apolitical Christian pacifism that withdraws from politi

cal life. Niebuhr's highest ideal is the disinterested, heedless, self-sacrificing

perfect love of Christ. Love is the only absolute norm for Niebuhr; it is the

ultimate referent by which all human actions are to be judged. Niebuhr

thus takes a very demanding view of the ethic of Jesus, both in seeing self-

sacrificial love as its core and in interpreting love as a pure and heedless

self-sacrifice. He sees the ethic of Jesus as an ethic of selfless giving that

condemns every form of self-assertion. He interprets that ethic in such a

perfectionist manner that to conform to it becomes the "impossible pos

sibility."1 No human action or motive can ever conform to it, though it re

mains the standard for the motives and actions of all individuals. Niebuhr

sees guilt even in the reluctant use of the minimum force to resist an evil

aggressor who is wreaking havoc. To Niebuhr, the selfless love of God and

of others implies that one ought never do harm to anyone.

Christian Realism

The Christian ideal is one strand of Niebuhr's ethic. The other is the Chris

tian recognition of the inevitable human failure to live up to it. At the heart

of realism is constraint: the realist claims to perceive disagreeable aspects

of reality, disagreeable because they present obstacles to the realization of

194 COLM MCICEOOH

our goals. The realist claims to take full account of the resistance of reality

to his or her ideals and claims, too, that the idealist does not. Central to

realism then is a certain degree of pessimism, the product of a recognition

that reality poses problems for the implementation of ideals. This pessi

mism need not be total; the obstacles that reality presents to our goals may

not be completely intractable. But realism is distinguished by its recogni

tion that the circumstances of choice will always be constraining to some

significant degree. The constraints on political choice mean that we must

sacrifice some of our ideals if we are to achieve any of our goals. The realist

accepts that not all of our goals can be achieved and that many are achiev

able only by means we would rather not use.

Niebuhr's Christian realism highlights the significant and ineradica

ble constraints on our freedom of action in politics and international rela

tions that are rooted in human nature. The highest Christian goal is love

and the most fundamental and powerful constraint on the achievement

of this goal arises from the fallen nature of human beings. The greatest

realist in the Christian tradition, Augustine, developed the view of hu

man nature that was to be the foundation of Niebuhr's approach to poli

tics. The concept of original sin, established at the heart of Christianity

by Augustine, asserts both the inevitability of sin and human responsibil

ity for it.9 Niebuhr's attentions were focused on this fundamental Chris

tian doctrine by the neo-orthodox theology of the Swiss theologian Karl

Barth though the American liberal criticized Barthian neo-orthodoxy as

a "new kind of fundamentalism" that lent itself to political conservatism.'0

It was Niebuhr's rediscovery of the doctrine of original sin that provided

the basis for his claim that pacifism as a political program reflects a per

fection that humans do not have. Even to claim that the ethics of nonresis

tance are possible for human beings is to tempt us to pretend that we are

God, not human.

Sin comes from our refusal to accept our inherent human limitations

and the perennial insecurity that is basic to our nature. Original sin re

suits not from our finitude and imperfection but from our anxiety about

our finitude and imperfection, which is made possible by our freedom and

which expresses itself in pride and pretension. The anxiety that Niebuhr

detects at the heart of the human condition results in a situation similar

to that described in international politics as a security dilemma in which

the attempt to lessen one's own insecurity only deepens that of one's fel

lows, with the paradoxical result that the instability and the risk of conflict

REINHOLD NIEBUHR'S CHRISTIAN REALLSM/CHRISTIAN IDEALISM 195

is heightened. To Niebuhr, the insecurity of human individuals is spiritual

as well as physical. The result is a more profound version of Hobbes's state

of nature and also a more pessimistic one. It is more profound in that the

insecurity in human life goes to the very root of our being, our position in

creation, being at once in the natural world and transcending it. It is more

pessimistic in that no full solution is possible. Insecurity is the human lot

because of the ambiguous human condition at the juncture of freedom

and necessity, both creatures and creators of our world. No sovereign can

eliminate it. Both Niebuhr and Hobbes highlight human anxiety and in

security; to Hobbes, the resultant seeking of power by all means at one's

disposal is a natural right; to Niebuhr, it is a sin. Of this human insecurity,

Niebuhr writes: "In short, man, being both free and bound, both limited

and limitless, is anxious. Anxiety is the inevitable concomitant of the par

adox of freedom and the finiteness in which man is involved. Anxiety is

the external precondition of sin. It is the inevitable spiritual state of man,

standing in the paradoxical situation of freedom and finiteness."1'

This condition of anxiety is the occasion for sin but not the cause of it;

rather it is our refusal to accept the insecurity that is fundamental to the

human condition which results in all human life being involved in the sin

of seeking security at the expense of other life. Like Pascal, Niebuhr sees

original sin as the mystery that makes human beings comprehensible to

themselves; it is the most accurate description and explanation of our na

ture as human beings2

This perception of human nature has implications for our social and

political life. We are incurably creative and so our history is dynamic,

moving, creative. We have freedom over both the past and the present, we

can break old forms, transform them, and establish new ones. This free

dom, combined with our rational capacities, our moral urges, and our im

pulse for survival and well-being, means that there are indeterminate pos

sibilities for higher levels of rational and moral insight, of technical and

social development, and of freedom and justice. But there are limits to the

new and morally better structures that may be formed. Though humans

have indeterminate possibilities, we can never alter our ontological struc

ture as both creature and self-transcendent. No final or permanent society

is conceivable in history, and no particular social order can be regarded as

permanent or stable. The spiritual creativity of humans, which is part of

our essential nature, transcends any form of social cohesion and thus any

society is subject to change, transformation, dissolution.

196 COLM MCKEOGH

A Dualist Approach

For Niebuhr, the fundamental feature of reality is its paradoxical and self-

contradictory nature. The approach to political reality that he adopts is a

dualist one. The principal dualism that characterizes Niebuhr's approach

to social and political ethics is one of Christian realism and Christian

idealism. Such an approach, he believed, would take account both of our

highest ideals and of the stark realities of politics. Only an approach to

politics that is both realistic and moral could yield an "adequate political

morality":

An adequate political morality must do justice to the insights of both

moralists and political realists. It will recognize that human society

will never escape social conflict, even though it extends the areas of so

cial cooperation. It will try to save society from being involved in end

less cycles of futile conflict, not by an effort to abolish coercion in the

life of collective man, but by reducing it to the minimum, by counseling

the use of such types of coercion as are most compatible with the moral

and rational factors in human society, and by distinguishing between

the purposes and ends for which coercion is used.'3

Niebuhr's aim is for an approach that neither abandons hope nor de

ludes itself that progress will be quick or easy or painless. Hans Morgen

thau wrote that, in general, Western civilization has devised two intellec

tual instruments to reconcile Christianity and politics: the first reinterprets

Christian ethics to make them fit the political facts, the second describes

political events as better than they are.'4 Niebuhr, however, rejects both the

dilution of Christianity and the misrepresentation of politics. He does not

compromise the commands of Christian ethics in any way; indeed, his in

terpretation of the ethic of Jesus is absolute and starkly uncompromising.

Nor does he downplay the immorality of the political act; again, Niebuhr is

uncompromising in his description of the inherent immorality of the po

litical act. He presents the conflict between politics and morality in a full

light. He shows the impossibility of reconciling them and yet this is what

he then attempts to do. Niebuhr thus rejects the contention that the con

flict between politics and Christian morals is irreconcilable, and that there

can be no such thing as a "Christian statesman." In contrast, he insists that

Christianity cannot reject politics.

The dualism of Niebuhr's approach has been described as a "tenuous

metaphysical proposition fraught with inconsistencies."5 Indeed, Niebuhr

REINHOLD NIEDUHR'S CHRISTIAN REALISM/CHRISTIAN IDEALISM 197

acknowledged that a realist theory of politics would not be a consistent

one; he wrote that he "abhor[red] consistency as a matter of principle be

cause history seems to prove that absolute certainty usually betrays into

some kind of absurdity."16 Consistent theories oversimplify reality. A sim

plified political theory will not solve the problems of international politics

but may foster dangerous beliefs in certainty and in perfect solutions. To

Niebuhr's eyes, political idealism tries to negate the fundamentally self-

contradictory nature of political reality. It simplifies political reality in its

attempt to maintain a clear and unambiguous sense of the world. In con

trast, political realism, confronted by a complex reality, accepts it as ir

reducibly complex and self-contradictory. Niebuhr's aim in his political

theory was to acknowledge fully the paradoxes, ironies, and tragedies of

reality. In approaching political reality we are forever confronting the dis

crepancy between our ideals and the prevailing situation, between our as

pirations and our attainments, between justice and power. Niebuhr's du

alism accepted this discrepancy as the cause and character of politics; it

worked toward an understanding of this discrepancy and endeavored to

set and attain limited goals within the framework of it. It recognized its

own limits and admitted that there were no permanent solutions to politi

cal problems. Prescriptively, it emphasized self-criticism and pragmatism.

Niebuhr adopted a dualist approach as the only one that could make

sense of the facts, tensions, and contradictions of human existence. It

might not have been intellectually defensible but it was pragmatically nec

essary. Niebuhr's dualism is not a straightforward one that requires Chris

tians to act by one set of rules in their personal life and by another in

their civic life. Instead, his approach takes two perspectives on all actions,

whether they are acts of state or of the individual, the two perspectives of

Christian realism and Christian perfectionism. The former has justice as

its highest norm; the latter love. All acts, whether of state or of the individ

ual, are to be criticized from both perspectives. An action that meets the

requirements of the Christian realist perspective will still be found want

ing from the perfectionist one.

There is thus an ineradicable tension between the requirements of the

two ethics. One takes account of the realities of fallen humans in a sinful

world; the other is transcendent and other-worldly. Niebuhr did not believe

it possible for humans to act always in accordance with the standards of

Christian perfectionism; he went so far in an interview as to claim boldly

that "only mothers, martyrs, mystics and monastics can perform acts of

self-sacrifice." 17 If there is little chance of the perfectionist ethic motivating

198 COLM MCKEOGH

the acts of individuals, then there is much less chance of it influencing the

acts of groups, for in groups, Niebuhr holds, human selfishness is magni

fied. In a realist vein, he stresses time and time again that there is almost

no possibility for moral action by groups. This he does to prevent our op

timism from deluding us about the moral potential of collective behavior.

Nations cannot adhere to the morality of individuals; love is an impossibil

ity in inter-group relations. The proof of this is that one cannot point to a

national policy that persists in going beyond national self-interest. A pure

self-sacrificing love is not a possibility for groups for no "nation, or any

other group for that matter, will ever sacrifice itself for another."t8 Nations

never commit suicide, nor should they. Neither the leaders nor the citizens

of a nation ought to conclude, from the law of love, that they should aban

don all their responsibilities and sacrifice all their interests.

To Niebuhr, neither Christian realism nor Christian idealism is ade

quate alone. Neither love nor justice is sufficient on its own. Love can never

take the place of justice, even under the best possible conditions. Love is

the only absolute but to try to live entirely by love and to discard the struc

tures of justice is to risk destroying love, for we need structures of justice

to protect people from love that can be biased and misdirected. Love with

out justice can be harmful even within the family or the church: justice is

always needed too as a guide to the ordering of any relations, Socially and

politically, love is not enough because individual goodness does not solve

any issue of social justice. To do this we need structures of justice and

rights. Therefore, in the process of building communities, every impulse

of love must be transformed into an impulse of justice. Justice must be the

first instrument of love.19

Yet justice alone is never enough, either. We cannot dismiss love from

social and international ethics because justice requires love in order to

overcome the inevitable bias of self-interest. Niebuhr writes that a justice

that is only justice is less than justice; what is needed is an "imaginative

justice, that is, love that begins by espousing the rights of the other rather

than the self" if a modicum of fairness is to be achieved.2° Justice, as the

calculation of rights and the discrimination between competing claims,

needs reason and yet that reason is corrupted by self-interest. Love can

overcome that bias and corruption. So love is not irrelevant to justice: it es

tablishes the viewpoint from which all norms and structures of justice are

to be judged, from which their ends may be recognized as proximate and

not ultimate, and their loyalties as parochial rather than universal.

REINHOLD NIEBUHE'S CHRISTIAN REALISM/CHRISTIAN IDEALISM 199

A Productive Tension

The product of Niebuhr's dualist approach is a constant tension between

its two elements. An action that seems to approach the requirements of the

realist ethic will fall far short of the demands of the perfectionist one. This

tension is fundamental and permanent: it cannot be resolved or lessened.

The idealism and the realism cannot be synthesized, reconciled, or harmo

nized. The permanent tension between ideals and realities is, to Niebuhr,

the essence ofhuman life on earth. This approach, which sets up two stan

dards by which all acts are to be judged, allows Niebuhr to meet his aim

of applying Christian morality to political reality without doing an injus

tice to either. He does not water down or corrupt the ethic of pure love in

order to make it applicable to the interactions of groups and nations. Nor

does he overstate the possibilities of moral action in politics. The tension

between the two ethics produces a constant self-criticism of all political

action and an awareness of its moral limitations. More important, the ten

sion urges the political actor to always go further and to be more creative

in seeking the coincidence of the national self-interest with the interests of

other nations.

The tension between Niebuhr's realism and his perfectionism has at

least four productive consequences for political action. First, the univer

salist and idealist perspective reduces the bias in our perception of po

litical and moral issues. There is always a danger that the realist ethic will

conceive the national interest too narrowly, but the universalist ethic helps

the political actor to realize that our destinies are intertwined and that a

narrow conception of the national interest will be self-defeating.

Second, the ethic based on love motivates the actor to find the point of

coincidence between the interests of the nation and the values that tran

scend those interests. Niebuhr's realism accepts that the national leader

ship cannot pursue policies that jeopardize the national interest but he

wishes them to recognize that, since all nations live under a common peril,

they must pursue policies that transcend, as they fulfill, the national inter

est. Niebuhr sees a common weakness among the adherents of realism in

that "they usually do not go far enough in meeting new problems and situ

ations. They are so conscious of the resistance in history to new ventures,

and are so impressed by the perennial problems of politics, which manifest

themselves on each new level of history, that they are inclined to discount

both the necessity and the possibility of new political achievements."2' The

200 COLM MCKEOGFI

higher ethic both motivates and assists the realist to view the national in

terest in a broader, more objective, and more long-term manner. Though

prudence alone may motivate the search for justice, religion adds both a

broader perspective, a stronger motivation, and greater staying power to

that unending quest: "justice... is on the whole an achievement of ratio

nal calculation. The will to do justice ultimately has a religious root and no

rational reason can be given why a man ought to be just, unless it be the

prudential one that injustice will finally destroy its beneficiaries as well as

its victims."22

A third productive consequence of the interaction between the two eth

ics is that idealism can stop realism from decaying into cynicism. Realism

is based on an acknowledgment that we must come to terms with the harsh

facts. of political reality; cynicism arises when these facts are accepted as

setting the standards for conduct. Niebuhr detected such cynicism in

many other realists of the time; for example, he agreed with George Ken-

nan's rejection of the "moralistic-legalistic" approach to international poli

tics and foreign policy but thought that "Kennan's solution for the problem

of our pretentious idealism is a return to the concept of `national inter

est.' He thinks that this concept should guide our foreign policy on the

grounds that we must not pretend to know more than what is good for us.

This modesty is important. But egotism is not the cure for an abstract and

pretentious idealism. Preoccupation with national interest can quickly de

generate into moral cynicism even if it is originally prompted by moral

modesty."23 The perfectionist ethic can stop the realist ethic from decaying

into cynicism, by judging all political realities and acts from a higher per

spective and showing how they all fall short of the ultimate norm. Niebuhr

believes too that a religious stance is required to give meaning to crisis and

to avert despair: "those who have not this key to the mystery of life and of

God are tempted. . . to be either complacent or hysterical when confronted

with the evils of history."24 Christianity does not guarantee that good will

triumph over evil in history, but it does assure one that evil will not tri

umph over God's designs.25

A fourth and final impact of the perfectionist ethic on the realist ethic

is to stop the latter from leading to moral pretension. States claim that they

cannot act beyond their own interests, yet when they go to war they can

claim to be fighting for universal values such as democracy, freedom, or

civilization. No action of the state, when viewed from the higher perspec

tive, can be seen as a moral act. The idealist perspective reveals the self

interest that underlies all political action, however virtuous it may seem.

REINHOLD NIEBUHR'S CHRISTIAN REALISM/CHRISTIAN IDEALISM 201

In these ways, Niebuhr's realist/idealist approach helps the actor to deal

with the paradoxical realities of politics. The realist ethic urges the politi

cal actor to be aware of power and self-interest and to seek the overlap of

interest and principle. However, this realist ethic remains under criticism

from the perfectionist ethic that has love as its ultimate value. By seeking

justice through a broad conception of the national interest, the political

leader may satisfy the realist ethic but never the perfectionist one. Prom

the higher perspective of Christianity, one could always do better. The

higher ethic provides the constant self-criticism of motives and question

ing of means. It ensures we never claim moral purity for any political act

and that we remain always self-critical.

The Tragedy of Politics

Niebuhr's dualist approach yields a sense of the inevitable tragedy of poli

tics. Often in politics, one must do wrong either way. Guilt is unavoidable.

The most we can realistically aim for is justice, and the achievement of any

degree of justice requires the use of power. Justice, whether within society

or between nations, must be based on a balance of power. This balance of

power implies a conflict of wills, a contest of interests in which gross in

justice is avoided only because the contending forces are evenly matched.

Injustices must usually be corrected through the vehement resentments

of their victims. This is even more so in international relations where the

cause of justice is even more precarious: unscrupulous nations are pun

ished only if sufficient power is aligned alongside moral condemnation.

Justice relies on power and yet power corrupts justice.

This moral ambiguity of politics implies the inevitable guilt of all in

volved in politics. The paradox of political and social action is that moral

responsibility requires us to take sides and to use power, which is sinful.

Justice means the calculation of rights and often the taking of sides for

the weak and against the strong. The result is that it "is not possible to en

gage in any act of collective opposition to collective evil without involv

ing the innocent with the guilty." Yet we must engage in political action

and in the use of power against others for we "cannot be good unless we're

responsible, and the minute we're responsible, we're involved in compro

mise."27 That we must be responsible for our common guilt does not annul

our responsibility to strive for relative justice.

Central to the tragedy of politics is the inability to act in history without

sin. For there will always be selfishly used power and therefore a responsi

202 COLM MCKEOGR

bilityto use countervailing power. The use of that countervailing power is,

from the perspective of a total love of others, sinful. Niebuhr's perfection

ist interpretation of the ethic of Jesus implies that all use of power in the

name of justice falls short of the ideal of love and is therefore sinful. It re

mains our moral responsibility to counter the power of others yet this im

plies if we do so effectively that we will inflict harm on them. From the

perspective of love, to inflict harm on others is to sin.

The result of this is Niebuhr's tragic view of human history. A clear

conscience is unattainable, through political involvement or through po

litical noninvolvement. Often we will find ourselves in a position where

both action and inaction will lead to harm being done to others. Those

who wield political power are unavoidably culpable, yet Niebuhr criticizes

equally those who have sought to keep their hands clean by staying out of

the morally ambiguous arena of politics. Any attempt to avoid the guilt of

political involvement is itself immoral: "we cannot purge ourselves of the

sin and guilt in which we are involved by the moral ambiguities of poli

tics without also disavowing responsibility for the creative possibilities of

justice."28

Poilticat Action

It is not possible to move in history without becoming tainted with guilt.

How then is one to act in politics and international relations? How does

the productive tension between irreconcilable realism and perfectionism

work in practice? Niebuhr refused to criticize national leaders for defend

ing national interests; political leaders are responsible to national and lo

cal constituencies arid must give voice to national and local interests. To

the end of his days he was skeptical of utopian thinkers who presented the

possibilities of transcending the national interest as greater than they ac

tually were. He repeated frequently that nations could never go beyond the

area of congruence between their national self-interest and a concern for

the needs of other peoples or of the world community as a whole. But he

was critical, not only of moralists who preached the transcending of the

national interest, but also of national leaders who viewed the national in

terest too narrowly, with insufficient and with short-term horizons.

Niebuhr accepted the pursuit of self-interest as an ineradicable feature

of human beings and their groups. He recognized that nations do support

universal values and principles but only when they accord with their per

ceived self-interest: "Every nation is guided by self-interest and does not

REINHOLD NIEBUHR'S CHRISTIAN REALISM/CHRISTIAN IDEALISM 203

support values which transcend its life, if the defense of these values mi-perils its existence. A statesman who sought to follow such a course would

be accused of treason. On the other hand nations do become the bearers of

values which transcend their national interests."29

Nations must act on the basis of self-interest, but that self-interest can

coincide with the global interest. No nation is good enough to do what is

right unless its sense of duty is compounded with its sense of survival.30

Niebuhr's repeated assertions that the national interest is, and must be, at

the heart of national policy would seem to leave little scope for morality

in foreign policy. But his conception of the national interest is a distinc

tive one. He writes: "Nations are, on the whole, not generous. A wise self-

interest is usually the limit of their moral achievements; though it is worth

noting that nations do not achieve a wise self-interest if generous impulses

do not help to drive them beyond the limits of a too-narrow self-interest."31

Niebuhr cites a "wise self-interest" as often the limit of a nation's moral

achievement; crucially, though, the true self-interest of a nation is more

than just a narrow exclusive national interest. All nations share an interest

in peace and order; the wise see this. Thus, he claims, it is not in any na

tion's self-interest to be selfish,

Underlying all his recommendations to national leaders and policy

makers is the beliefthat the real interest ofnations is not a narrow, exclusive

one, and that the national interest, when conceived only from the stand

point of the self-interest of the nation, is bound to be defined "too narrowly

and therefore to be self-defeating."32 A too narrowly defined national inter

est is one that fails to consider those national interests that are bound up in

a web ofmutual interests with other nations. Thus, to Niebuhr, a consistent

emphasis on self-interest is as counterproductive in national life as in indi

vidual life: "a consistent self-interest on the part ofa nation will work against

its interests because it will fail to do justice to the broader and longer-term

interests which are involved with the interests of other nations."33

Niebuhr insists that international politics is not a zero-sum game and

that national interests are not mutually exclusive. Underlying this claim

was not just his faith in a benevolent creator, The existence of nuclear

weapons made it clear that peace was in the interests of all nations; jus

tice too was a common national interest, as there could be no stable peace

without justice. Niebuhr's advice to all national policy makers was this:

always seek the overlap of national and global interests, and never accept

that conflicts of real interests and therefore war are inevitable. He urged

on them a "wise self-interest informed by loyalty to principles transcend-

204 CaLM MCKEOGH

ing national interests" and stressed that the art of statecraft is to find the

point of concurrence between the "parochial and the general interest, be

tween the national and the international common good."34 This is not just

the art of statecraft, it is the moral duty of all involved in national policy.

Political realism alone is not enough to achieve this, for prudence alone

will often define the national interest too narrowly. It will approach com

mon problems from the perspective of a particular interest and will fail

to seek the longer-term solution, What are also needed, says Niebuhr, are

moral and religious perspectives in order to widen our conception of inter

est and also to motivate us to seek the coincidence of national and global

interests. Both reason and the religious spirit are required to inspire a

broader interpretation of the nation's interests. To Niebuhr, the pursuit

of the national interest will never in itself lead to a recognition of the co

incidence of interests. One must be inspired by the religious ideals of love

and justice to search for and to recognize the coincidence of interests. One

must aim for something more than justice if one is to achieve justice.

A national leader who got the balance right, in the domestic political

circumstances of his time, was Abraham Lincoln, Niebuhr's hero from an

early age the German pastor's son grew up in an Illinois town named af

ter the president, the Niebuhr house being less than a mile from the court

where Lincoln had argued cases as a circuit lawyer. Lincoln was the model

ofan able politician whose religious humility allowed him to fight for what

he believed to be right without feeling the need to portray the other side as

wholly wrong. He combined a political shrewdness without the cynicism

Niehuhr detected iii Roosevelt's 1936 campaign with a religious perspec

tive without the moralizing that turned Niebuhr against Wilson. That re

ligious perspective made him aware that God's purposes were partly con

tradicted by the moral issues of the vast historical drama in which Lincoln

was playing his part, and yet were not irrelevant to it. It brought to light the

element of pretension in the idealism of both sides and allowed Lincoln to

remain modest about the virtue and wisdom of his own side. It gave to the

president's stance of "malice towards none and charity for all" a firm basis

in contrition about the human frailties and vanities that were common to

both sides to the conflict. "The prophets of righteousness who would make

no compromises could not have achieved their ideals but for the states

men who did make compromises," a young Niebuhr wrote in 1918. "Abra

ham Lincoln was just as necessary to the abolition movement as William

Lloyd Garrison. Christian statesmen are essential to the kingdom of God

as Christian prophets."35

REINHOLD NIEBUHR'S CHRISlIAN REALISM/CHRISTIAN IDEALISM 205

As an example of a too narrow national interest in international rela

tions, Niebuhr cites the post-1918 fixation of the United States on German

debt repayment and reparation: self-interest, conceived in inadequate and

short-term ways, deflected the true interests of the world and of the United

States itself. A generous policy of debt liquidation would have helped the

Weimar leadership to rebuild the German economy, to establish democ

racy, and to reenter the community of nations.36 The Marshall Plan, on the

other hand, is an example of the wise self-interest that Niebuhr sought.

The reconstruction of Germany was in the long-term self-interest of the

United States as well as in the broader world interest, yet it took a great deal

of generosity for that to be seen. Bitterness, narrow nationalism, and a de

sire for vengeance could all too easily have stood in its way: "Our aid need

not, however, be prompted purely by either humanitarian concern for the

starving or by concern for the preservation of political liberty in Europe,

though it is to be hoped that these motives will be operative. We must fur

nish aid also in the interest of our own economic health. . . It is highly sig

nificant that motives of self-interest thus come to the support of a policy

which generosity alone might well prompt. It is good that this is so, since

even the best nations are incapable of pure generosity."37

Yet, though the plan stands as a prime example of a Niebuhrian politi

cal act, it should not be seen as primarily a moral act. One should not claim

too much moral quality for what is still a political action. Niebuhr wrote at

the time: "As is always the case in international relations, what is called for

is not an act 9f benevolence but of wise self-interest."38 The plan was a case

of enlightened self-interest united with a concern for the general welfare;

as such it stands as an example of the most attainable virtue of nations.

American entry into World War II provides another example of na

tional self-interest coinciding with the greater world interest. In 1941, when

some voices were calling for the president to be more circumspect in his

neutrality, Niebuhr was calling for the repeal of the Neutrality Act and for

material assistance to Britain and her allies.39 But he was not, at this stage,

seeking direct American participation in the war against Germany. 1-le

made it clear that such action was indeed demanded if the United States

was to be truly responsible but, ever the realist, he acknowledged that the

interests of the United States had not yet been imperiled in a sufficiently

obvious manner for the administration to be able to unite the nation in a

declaration of war. Fron-i the moral perspective, the United States should

have entered the war against Germany; it was in the self-interest of the

United States to enter the war if that interest was interpreted in an enlight

206 COLM MCKEOGH

ened and far-seeing manner. But, practically, American involvement had

to wait upon a clearer perception of that interest and responsibility. The at

tack upon Pearl Harbor in December 1941 united the nation in the war ef

fort and in the fulfillment of its responsibilities. This example throws light

on the relationship that Niebuhr sees between a nation's self-interest and

a nation's ethical responsibilities: a nation is loyal to ideals that transcend

its life, but it can act in loyalty to these ideals only if its vital interests are

not prejudiced; it can do so more easily when the ideals and the interests

coincide.40

In a 1941 article, Niebuhr defines immoral behavior on the part of a

nation in the following terms: "The essence of immorality is the denial or

evasion of moral responsibility. An irresponsible nation is an immoral na

tion, while a nation that is becoming dimly aware of its responsibilities and

acts accordingly is moving towards Niebuhr defines morality

as the recognition of the interdependence of life. This applies to persons

as to nations, as both live in a web of relations with their fellows. A nation

best fulfills its obligations by pursuing policies that recognize that its wel

fare is bound up with that of other nations. In that 1941 article, in which he

was urging the repeal of the Neutrality Act, Niebuhr was arguing against

isolationists, neutralists, and pacifists, and he wrote: "Do-nothingness for

the sake of peace is not moral. It is pure escapism in a world where na

tions can escape no longer from the ethical consequences of their inter

dependence."42 This last sentence contains a key phrase that illuminates

Niebuhr's view of politics and morality: the ethical consequences of their

interdependence. The economic, technical, and commercial developments

of the twentieth century had ethical implications. Because of growing in

terdependence between nations, the world is closer to a community of na

tions; consequently, nations now have new and expanded moral responsi

bilities to each other. To deny those responsibilities is immoral as well as

counterproductive. Because of greater interdependence, an old-style nar

rowly defined national interest in terms of power and interest is no longer

any nation's true self-interest.

Conclusion

Niebuhr was very much a man of his time, who rose to prominence with a

message that resonated throughout his country at that juncture in its his

tory. Yet his approach has relevance today as his warnings about human

nature, politics, and the scope for moral action in our collective life still

REINHOLD NIEBUHR'S CHRISTIAN REALISM/CHRISTIAN IDEALISM 207

hold. A truly realistic approach is one that takes account of the highest

yearnings of human beings as well as their selfishness and recalcitrance.

We must acknowledge both how far short of the ideal the current inter

national economic and political order is and how great the obstacles to

progress are. The tension between ideals and realities is the perennial stuff

of politics, but the relationship between realism and idealism cannot be

precisely fixed. With changing times, a new balance of realism and ideal

ism is required in our outlook and in our actions. Niebuhr's own siding

with capitalism and bourgeois democracy in the 1930S was pragmatic: he

still considered them to be selfish and less than the highest at which hu

mankind should aim. It was in the face of a threat to capitalist civilization

from an even worse system that he swung his support behind the old or

der. To Niebuhr, for whom the idealism of the Christian gospel is required

to save us from cynicism and complacency and the realism of the Chris

tian faith to save us from sentimentality, it was clear where the danger lay

in his own time. "In America at least," Niebuhr wrote in 1942, "the dan

gers of a perverse sentimentality have been greater than the perils of cyni

cism."43 Times have changed and the reverse may now be the case. Indeed,

the imbalance of power in the world today can only lead to injustice. Yet

with vision, political leaders may see how the interests of their own people

are best served, in the long run, by the creation of a more just international

economic and social order. As ever, the attempt to secure only the national

interest will fail. Only the attempt to go beyond the national interest to

ward justice will effectively secure the national interest. These failings of

foreign policy are never just failures ofreason. Human reaon fails because

it is always biased, partial, and self-interested. It is inevitably biased, not

simply because of stupidity, but because of sin: "There is something more

than mere ignorance in this stupidity," Niebuhr commented in the 1940s.

"The stupidity of sin is in this darkness."44 The sin is the original sin of all

human individuals and groups: their pride and self-righteousness and ar

rogance and narrow egotism. Human egotism cannot be wished away and

perfect peace and justice will never prevail in human politics. Yet with

wisdom and courage, real opportunities can be recognized and signifi

cant steps taken to enhance the well-being of nations and the peace of the

world. As Niebuhr forecast during World War II:

The new international community will be constructed neither by the

pessimists, who believe it impossible to go beyond the balance of power

principle in the relation of nations to each other; nor by the cynics, who

208 COLM MCKEOGH

would organize the world by the imposition of imperial authority with

out regard to the injustices which inevitably flow from arbitrary and ir

responsible power; nor yet by the idealists, who are under the fond il

lusion that a new level of historic development will emancipate history

from these vexing problems. The new world must be built by resolute

men who "when hope is dead will hope by faith"; who will neither sek

premature escape from the guilt of history, nor yet call the evil, which

taints all their achievements, good.45

Niebuhr's famous and realist prayer of 1943, which asks God for the

grace to accept with serenity the things that cannot be changed, courage to

change the things that should be changed, and the wisdom to distinguish

the one from the other, applies to our political endeavors as to any others.16

To a political realist, it remains the nature of this world, as Woody Allen

reminds us, that the lion may lie down with the lamb but the lamb won't

get much sleep.

NOTES

Epigraph: Woody Allen, Without Feathers New York: Random House, 1972, p. 25.

i. Niebuhr, "Why I Am Not a Christian," The Christian Century 44 December s, 1927:

1483.

2. Niebuhr, "A Critique of Pacifism," The Atlantic Monthly 139 May 1927: 641, 640.

. Niebuhr, "Power and fustice," Ghristicsnily and Society 8 Winter 1942: 10.

. Niebuhr, "Let the Liberal Churches Stop Fooling Themselves," The Christian Century 48

March 25, 1931: 402.

5. Niehuhr, "Germany Must Be Told!" The Christian Century 50 August 9, 1933: 1014-15.

6. Niebuhr, Reflections on the End of an Era New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1934,

p. 247.

. Niebuhr, Christianity and Power Politics New York: Charles Scribners Sons, 1940, p. 3'.

8. Niebuhr, An Interpretation of Christian Ethics London: Student Christian Movement

Press, 1936, p. 68. Niebuhr's famous description of love as such is rejected by John Howard

Yoder. The ideal of love has been lived up to in history by Jesus, writes the Mennonite pacifist,

and Christians as a community should bear witness to this. Love, and love alone, therefore,

should motivate Christians; John H. Yoder, The Original Revolution: Essays on Christian Paci

fism Scottdale, Pa.: Herald Press, 1971, pp. 47, 52-84, 115.

9. Niebuhr, The Nature and Destiny ofMan, vol. 1 London: Nisbet, 1941, p. 256.

so. Richard W. Fox, Reinhold Niebuhr: A Biography New York: Pantheon, 1985, p. 117.

ii. Niebuhr, Nature and Destiny ofMan, vol. i, p. 182.

12. Niebuhr, Faith and History: A Comparison of Christian and Modern Views of History

London: Nisbet, 1938, p. 114.

13. Niebuhr, Moral Man and Jmmoral Society New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1932,

p. 234.

14. 1-1. R. Landon, ed., Reinhold Niebuhr: A Prophetic Voice in Our Time Greenwich, Conn.:

Seabury Press, 1962, p. 102.

REINHOLD NIEIIUHR'S CHRISTIAN REALISM/CHRISTIAN IDEALISM 209

15. Daniel F. Rice, Reinhold Niebuhr and John Dewey: An American Odyssey Albany: State

University of New York Press, 1993, P. 6.

16. Niebuhr, "Pacifism and the Use of Force," The World Tomorrow 15 May 1928: 218.

17. Niebuhr and Hans Morgenthau, "The Ethics of War and Peace in the Nuclear Age," War!

Peace Report 7 February 1967: 3.

i8. Niebuhr, The Contribution of Religion to Social Work New York: Columbia University

Press, 1932, P. 92.

19. Niebuhr's claim that the Christian norm of love requires responsibility for tile social or

der is rejected by Yoder indeed, claims Yoder, in Niebuhr's approach social responsibility re

places love as the primary duty of the Christian. Niebuhr, Yoder asserts, lacks an adequate es

chatology when he sees the Christian's duty in trying to control history and helping it to turn

out right. Ultimately, Yoder is accusing Niebuhr of lacking an adequate faith in God, not a faith

that God would make things turn out right in human history in human terms, but a faith that,

even though may not turn out right in human history, there is still a reason for it. See John H.

Yoder, "Reinhold Niebuhr and Christian Pacifism," Mennonite Quarterly Review 29 April 1955:

10 1-17.

20. Niebuhr, "The Ethic of Jesus and the Social Problem," Religion in Lfe i Spring 5932:

200.

z, Niebuhr, "Plans for World Reorganization," Christianity and Crisis 2 October 19,1942: 4.

22. Niebuhr, "The Christian Perspective on the World Crisis," Christianity and Crisis 4

Mays, 1944: 3.

23. A comment on Kennan's American Diplomacy l900-s9so in Editorial Notes, Christianity

and Crisis ii October 29, 1951: 139.

24. Edmund Fuller, ed., The Christian Idea ofEducation New Haven: Yale University Press,

1957, p. 24; see also Niebuhr, "The Christian Perspective on the World Crisis," Christianity and

Crisis 4 May, i, 1944: 2-5.

25. Fuller, ed., The Christian Idea ofEducation, p. 241.

26. Niebuhr, "The Bombing of Germany," Christianity and Society 8 Summer 1943: 3.

27. Niebuhr to his classes at Union Seminary, New York, recorded in June C. Bingham,

Courage to Change: An Introduction to the Life and Thought of Reinhold Niebuhr New York:

Charles Scribners, 1961, p. 149.

28. Niebuhr, The Nature arid Destiny ofMan, vol. 2 London: Nisbet, 1943, p. 294.

29. Niebuhr, "The Good People of Britain," Radical Religion 4 Summer 1939: 7.

o. Niebuhr, "Our Responsibilities in 1942," Christianity and Crisis i January 12, 1942: 1.

31. Niebuhr, "Streaks of Dawn in the Night," Christianity and Crisis 9 December 12, 1942:

162.

32. Niebuhr, The World Crisis and American Responsibility: Analyses by Reinhold Niebuhr,

ed. Ernest W. Lefever New York: Association Press, 1958, p. 40.

Niebuhr, Christian Realism and Political Problems London: Faber and Faber, 1954,

p. 130.

34. Reported by Kenneth W. Thompson, "Towards Theory of International Politics," Ameri

can Political Science Review 49 September 1955: 741.

5. Niebuhr, Young Reinhold Niebuhr: His Early Writings 1911-1931, ed. William G. Chrystal

New York: Pilgrim Press, 1977, p.98; see also Niebuhr, The Irony ofAmerican History London:

Nisbet, 1952, Pp. 147-49.

36. Paul Merkeley, Reinhold Niebuhr: A Political Account London: McGill-Queens Univer

sity Press, 1975, p. uS.

Niebuhr, "The Marshall Plan," Christianity and Crisis 7 October 13, 1947: 2.

210 COLM MCKEOGH

38. Niebubr, "American Wealth and the World's Poverty," Christianity and Society 12 Au

tUmn 1947: 3.

Niebuhr, "Repeal the Neutrality Actl" ChrIstianity and Crisis i October 20, 1941: 1-2.

o. Niebuhr, Europe's Catastrophe and Christian Faith London: Nisbet, 1930, p. 40.

45. Niebuhr, "Repeal the Neutrality Act!" p. a.

42. Ibid.

43. Niebuhr, "The Churches and the War," Town Meetings of the Air August 27, 1942.

44. Niebuhr, Discerning the Signs of the Times: Sermonsfor Today and Tomorrow London:

Student Christian Movement Press, 5946, Pp. 51, 48.

5. Niebuhr, The Nature and Destiny ofMan, vol. 2, pp. 295-96.

46. Niebuhr, Justice and Mercy New York: Harper and Row, 1974, p. v; so popular did

Niebuhr's prayer become that, Fox reports, it was credited variously in the post-1945 years to

Marcus Aurelius, Francis of Assisi, and Friedrich Octinger; see Fox, Reinhold Niebuhr, p. 290.

lhe grace of God can change only some things, Niebuhr here suggests.

SUGGESTED READINGS

Bingham, June C. Courage to Change: An Introduction to the Life and Thought ofRein

hold Niebuhn New York: Charles Scribners, 1965.

Fox, Richard W. Reinhold Niebuhr: A Biography. New York: Pantheon, 1985.

Merkeley, Paul. Reinhold Niebuhr: A Political Account. London: McGill-Queens Uni

versity Press, 1975.

McKeogh, Coin,. The Political Realism ofReinhold Niebuhr. Basingstoke: Macmillan,

1997.

Niebuhr, Reinhold. Christianity and Power Politics. New York: Charles Scribner's

Sons, 1940.

Christian Realism and Political Problems. London: Faber and Faber, 1954.

"A Critique of Pacifism." The Atlantic Monthly 119 May 1927: 637-41.

"The Ethic of Jesus and the Social Problem." Religion in Lfe 1 Spring 1932:

198-208.

-. Faith and History: A Comparison of Christian and Modern Views of History.

London: Nisbet, 1938.

"Germany Must Be Told!" The Christian Century 50 August 9, 1933: 1014-15.

An Interpretation of Christian Ethics. London: Student Christian Movement

Press, 1936.

Justice and Mercy. New York: Harper and Row, 1974.

"Let the Liberal Churches Stop Fooling Themselves." The Christian Century 48

March 25, 1931: 402-4.

"The Marshall Plan." Christianity and Crisis 7 October 13, 1947: 2.

Moral Man and Immoral Society. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1932.

The Nature and Destiny ofMan. 2 vols. London: Nisbet, i9i and 1943.

"Power and Justice." Christianity and Society 8 Winter 1942: 9-10.

Reflections on the End ofan Era. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1934.

"Streaks of Dawn in the Night." Christianity and Crisis December 12, 1942:

162-64.

REINHOLD NIEBUHR'S CHRISTIAN REALISM/CHRISTIAN IDEALISM 211

Young Reinhold Niebuhr: His Early Writings 1911-1931. Edited by William 0.

Chrystal. New York: Pilgrim Press, 1977.

"Why I Am Not a Christian." The Christian Century 44 December 15, 1927:

1482-83.

Yoder John H. The Original Revolution: Essays on Christian Pacifism. Scottdale, Pa.:

Herald Press, 1971.

"Reinhold Niebuhr and Christian Pacifism." Mennonite Quarterly Review 29

April 1955: 101-17.