mystical experience as evidence

28
blternational Journalfor Philosophy of Religion 40: 19-46, (August 1996) 1996 KluwerAcademic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands. Mystical experience as evidence EVAN FALES Department of Philosophy, The University of lowa Thus the Lord used to speak to Moses face to face, as a man speaks to his friend... 'But', He said, 'you cannot see my face; for man shall not see me and live'. Ex. 33:11 & 20 Religious apologetics is perennially attracted to the idea that religious beliefs are arrived at in ways that are fundamentally on all fours with the procedures by means of which more mundane beliefs are generated and justified. If that is so, not only could the same conceptual tools be applied to the epistemic evaluation of both religious and mundane beliefs, but atheists and agnostics could be confronted (given certain sorts of evidence) with an unpleasant dilemma: either to treat mundane beliefs with the same skepti- cism, or to admit that the epistemic credentials of religious beliefs are - or at least could be - in good order. Perhaps the most natural application of this thought is to religious beliefs which are more or less directly the result of perceptual experiences - perceptual experiences whose putative objects are divine or supernatural. A class of such experiences lies ready to hand: mystical experiences, as they are often called. The philosophical challenge is to show, in terms of our best current understanding of epistemic justification generally, that such experiences do confer upon religious beliefs based on them the same sort of prima facie justification that sensory experience supplies for ordinary perceptual beliefs. William Alston's book Perceiving God gives this theme the most sophis- ticated treatment it has yet received. 1 Taking our reasoning from sense experience as a paradigm of empirical knowledge, Alston's strategy is to see how judgments based upon mystical experiences stack up against this standard. He proceeds by analyzing the major features of our ordinary cog- nitive practices with respect to sensory input, and then examines the extent to which analogous features can be found in the practices of mystics; that is, in the epistemic use they make of their spiritual experiences. Alston's con- clusion is that the analogies are quite close, on the whole, and that, with some reservations, it can therefore be said that beliefs derived from mystical experience are on roughly the same footing as ordinary empirical beliefs.

Upload: evan-fales

Post on 06-Jul-2016

213 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

blternational Journal for Philosophy of Religion 40: 19-46, (August 1996) �9 1996 KluwerAcademic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.

Mystical experience as evidence

EVAN FALES Department of Philosophy, The University of lowa

Thus the Lord used to speak to Moses face to face, as a man speaks to his f r iend. . . 'But', He said, 'you cannot see my face; for man shall not see me and live'. Ex. 33:11 & 20

Religious apologetics is perennially attracted to the idea that religious beliefs are arrived at in ways that are fundamentally on all fours with the procedures by means of which more mundane beliefs are generated and justified. If that is so, not only could the same conceptual tools be applied to the epistemic evaluation of both religious and mundane beliefs, but atheists and agnostics could be confronted (given certain sorts of evidence) with an unpleasant dilemma: either to treat mundane beliefs with the same skepti- cism, or to admit that the epistemic credentials of religious beliefs are - or at least could be - in good order. Perhaps the most natural application of this thought is to religious beliefs which are more or less directly the result of perceptual experiences - perceptual experiences whose putative objects are divine or supernatural. A class of such experiences lies ready to hand: mystical experiences, as they are often called. The philosophical challenge is to show, in terms of our best current understanding of epistemic justification generally, that such experiences do confer upon religious beliefs based on them the same sort of prima facie justification that sensory experience supplies for ordinary perceptual beliefs.

William Alston's book Perceiving God gives this theme the most sophis- ticated treatment it has yet received. 1 Taking our reasoning from sense experience as a paradigm of empirical knowledge, Alston's strategy is to see how judgments based upon mystical experiences stack up against this standard. He proceeds by analyzing the major features of our ordinary cog- nitive practices with respect to sensory input, and then examines the extent to which analogous features can be found in the practices of mystics; that is, in the epistemic use they make of their spiritual experiences. Alston's con- clusion is that the analogies are quite close, on the whole, and that, with some reservations, it can therefore be said that beliefs derived from mystical experience are on roughly the same footing as ordinary empirical beliefs.

20

But here we must be careful: Alston disavows the view that his argument is ultimately analogical, since he claims that each cognitive practice must be judged on its own merits and evaluated in terms of the standards which may be uniquely appropriate to it. Nevertheless, it is quite clear that Alston's argument trades on pushing certain analogies between the sensory domain and the spiritual one. The best way to understand this is to see Alston as insisting on similarities with respect to certain generic features that must characterize any acceptable cognitive practice whatsoever. 2

My plan is to examine two of the supposed parallels between the mystical and the sensory arenas which are central to Alston's project of establishing their similarity. I shall try to show that in the one case the parallel is very poor, and that in the other, it is, by Alston's own admission, very problematic whether the phenomenological facts required to establish the parallel are ones to which we, or even the mystics themselves, have sufficient access. These two difficulties alone, I will argue, suffice to put seriously in doubt Alston's claim of rough parity between sensory and mystical beliefs. 3

Alston goes to some pains to establish, in the first place, that mystical experiences are, at least often, perceptual experiences, and are therefore in a fundamental way on a par with sensory experience. Whether that is correct is the first issue. The second concerns the cognitive practices by means of which beliefs derived from perceptual experience are evaluated. Alston finds it useful to distinguish a variety of cognitive practices, largely in terms of the sort of input they utilize and the content of the beliefs which they generate as output. While acknowledging that any such classification is bound to involve some arbitrariness, Alston finds it useful to distinguish, amongst other major divisions, the cognitive practices associated with sense perception, memory, and a priori reasoning. To that list will be added the practices which take mystical experience as input and yield religious claims as output; mystical practice is usefully further subdivided into the practices associated with distinct religious traditions. Adopting Alston's terminology, let us speak of sensory practices (SP), mystical practices (MP), and, more specifically, of Christian mystical practices (CMP).

Here another terminological matter must be cleared up. Alston calls the spiritual experiences he wishes to discuss mystical experiences. The experi- ences he has in mind are ones that are arguably perceptual in character, and that are, more specifically, experiences that seem to their recipients to be expe- riences of the god of traditional theism - that is, a god of the sort worshipped by Jews, Christians, and Muslims. But this still leaves a great deal unspeci- fied. For example, such an experience might have a purely "inward" character, or it might be an experience with visual, auditory, or other sensory compo- nents, such as Paul is said to have had on the road to Damascus; or it might be a case of sensing the presence of God in a flower or a mountain landscape.

21

Alston's focus is upon spiritual experiences of the inward sort. 'It seems clear', he says, 'that a non-sensory appearance of a purely spiritual deity has a greater chance of presenting Him as He is than any sensory presenta- tion'. 4 But there is another, unstated, reason for this focus: it makes it possi- ble to distinguish MP more clearly from SE and to minimize the intrusion of the procedures we use to evaluate sense experience into ME Let's go along with this, though it raises questions no complete discussion of MP ought to omit. There is a further way in which description of these experi- ences and practices as mystical is misleading, however. As Alston recog- nizes, not all such experiences have as their putative object the theistic god or indeed any god or supernatural being at all. In view of this, while I shall retain Alston's acronyms 'MP' and 'CMP' for the cognitive practices in question, I shall describe the experiences under discussion as theophanies. And finally, it is to be understood, unless otherwise indicated, that when I use the term 'theophany' to refer to a putative perceptual experience of a theistic god, I am implying no commitment as to whether the experience is veridical or not - and hence no commitment as to whether there is such a being. This will permit me to avoid having always to speak of putative or apparent theophanies, and accords with Alston's own intentions.

I have not yet said which features of SP provide the basis for the second - and main - quarrel I have with Alston. There are two such features, but they are closely related. One is what Alston calls the overrider system. A claim about the physical world, whether based directly upon perceptual experience or the result of an inference, has, Alston thinks, prima facie credibility. But there may be grounds for doubt. A belief can be challenged - and, if challenged, defended in various ways.

For example, my claim to see a hackberry tree just outside the window can be defeated by presenting evidence which shows that I 've misidentified the tree, or that what I took to be a tree isn't a tree at all, or that I 'm hallucinating. Or, my claim can be defeated by showing that, even if there is a hackberry tree, my circumstances are such that I am in no position to ascertain this. 5 The overrider system for SP consists of those empirical and conceptual resources which enable such defeats to be generated, and which can be drawn upon to rebut defeaters, to defeat rebuttals, and so on. 6 Clearly, the importance, within SP, of these resources for appraisals of the reliability of particular empirical beliefs and of the practice as a whole, can scarcely be overestimated. Within the domain of scientific theory, the procedures to which Alston is alluding are central to issues of confirmation; they arise especially in connection with Duhem's Thesis. I shall have more to say about this presently.

The second feature of SP is its ability to provide self-support. That is, the use of SP leads to empirical findings which generate support for the conclu- sion that our cognitive apparatus, at least when operating in discoverably

22

favorable conditions, functions in such a way as to yield reliably true beliefs. Such support is supplied, for example, by investigations of the causal mech- anisms which mediate sense perception, by evolutionary arguments for the reliability of our cognitive mechanisms, and by other evidence which enables us to understand the strengths and limitations of those faculties. It could have turned out otherwise: using these faculties, we might have been led to the unfortunate conclusion that they are radically unreliable. But luckily, we are led to the opposite conclusion; 7 hence SP is self-supporting.

As Alston sees it, it is crucial for him to show that MP - and in particular CMP - also has the resources to generate an overrider system, and also can provide self-support. Nevertheless, Alston insists that it would be wrong- headed to evaluate these aspects of CMP in terms of the features which are central to an evaluation of their analogues in SP. I shall argue that he is mis- taken about this; that these requirements are necessarily intrinsic to any per- ceptual practice whose aim is to put us in touch with extramental reality. Because CMP cannot - or at any rate does not - adequately meet these requirements, it is seriously defective as a cognitive practice. We face, then, two questions. Do mystical experiences have perceptual content? And does MP have adequate resources for heading off doubts concerning the veridi- cality of mystical experiences?

1. The phenomenal content of mystical experiences

I turn now first to the question whether the theophanies (or at any rate some theophanies) can be considered to be putative non-sensory, direct apprehen- sions of God. Two preliminary questions need to be addressed. First, in virtue of what is it that theophanies can properly be said to be direct percep- tual experiences, as opposed to being, e.g., memories or purely intellectual episodes? And, second, what are the intrinsic qualitative or phenomenal characteristics which are distinctive of those experiences?

Alston acknowledges a distinction between direct or immediate perceptual awareness of an object, and indirect perceiving. Thus, in the case of sense perception, there is a difference between actually seeing an airplane, and seeing it on television or in a mirror. The former is a case of direct percep- tion, the latter of indirect perception, of seeing something (the plane) by virtue of seeing something else (the TV screen or mirror). 8

What is distinctive of perceptual experience, says Alston, is that perception involves a presentation, something being given to one. But there are grades of immediacy. Our own states of consciousness are absolutely immediate for us. But direct perceptual awareness of an extramental object is immedi- ate in a different sense. In direct perception of an extramental object, one is

23

aware, through a state of consciousness, of an object that is distinguishable from it. Thus, to say that someone has direct perceptual awareness of God is to say that he or she has an experience in which God is present in person and not in virtue of an awareness of any other object of perception; and that God is distinguishable from the experience itself. 9

Alston goes on - quite correctly - to insist that perceptual experience does involve something presented or given, which can be distinguished from (though its character may be influenced by) whatever conceptual means we employ in grasping and forming judgments about it. But this means that there must be something the given is intrinsically like. When an object is directly experienced, there must be some set of qualities which that object is presented as having.

So Alston has two tasks. First, he needs to show that at least some theo- phanies involve apparent presentations or confrontations with God; and second, he needs to show that there is something it is phenomenally like to experience such a confrontation. The two tasks are connected by the fact that there must be something that it is like to have an apparent theophany, if that theophany is to count as a perceptual experience.

A prima facie case for the presentational character of some non-sensory theophanies can be made by appeal to the fact that these experiences often seem to have that character, or at least, are so described. But then, what are these theophanies like? What qualifies is God presented as having? A natural suggestion would be that there is no way for someone who has not had such an experience to know this, anymore than a blind person could know what the visual experience of color is like. But surprisingly, Alston does not make this point; ~~ he focuses rather upon two difficulties which would arise, I take it, even for mystics. The first problem is that

. . . we are quite incapable of enumerating the basic phenomenal qualities of which 'divine phenomena' are configurations... We know quite a bit about the ways in which sensory experience depends in a regular way on its physical, physiological, and psychological conditions. We have dis- covered quite a bit about the stimulus conditions of various sensory qual- ities, and we have been able to subject the experience of those qualifies to a considerable degree of stimulus control . . . But nothing like this has happened with respect to the perception of God, nor is it at all likely to. We know nothing of the mechanisms of such perception, if indeed it is proper to talk of mechanisms here; nor can we grasp any useful regulari- ties in the conditions under which God will appear in one or another qua- litatively distinctive way to one's experience. . . Thus we lack the most elementary prerequisites for analyzing divine appearances into the phe- nomenal elements, cataloging them, associating them intersubjectively with names, dimensionalizing them, and so on. (PG, p. 49).

24

I have quoted Alston rather fully because what he says here is important not only to the present question, but to the power and precision any overrider system MP can hope to have. Alston's point is that even experienced mystics will have, apparently, little basis on which to compare the qualitative content of their theophanies. Color perceivers can learn to ascribe the color white to an object in a whole host of circumstances, both ones in which the object looks white and ones in which it does not, because whiteness is a publicly observable characteristic of publicly observable physical objects to which we can make common reference under relatively well-understood circumstances. The same does not apply, supposedly, to theophanies. 11

Yet in spite of having said this, Alston goes on to enumerate a number of qualities of theophanies. Drawing upon Catholic mystical traditions, he lists sensations that are described as being spiritual analogues to the bodily sen- sations of warmth and touch, fragrance, sight, and audition. So perhaps it is by way of analogies to intersubjectively verifiable sensory experience that mystics can communicate to other mystics - and to the wodd at large - the character of their theophanies. That would mark some progress; but it would make the communication of claims resulting from MP parasitic upon SP in a significant way. Nevertheless, the analogies are purely phenomenal; they do not imply similarity in the stimulus conditions.

What about the suspicion that there really are no such sense-analogous qualities presented by God to someone who experiences a theophany, that all of the qualities that characterize that state are affective ones: fear, or the feeling of being loved, or the like? This possibility worries Alston less that I think it should. Of course fear, or the feeling of being loved, won' t do at all as qualities of the sort Alston requires. These are emotional states of the subject, not qualities of a presented object, however closely they may be associated with the presentation of an object. Not only do they characterize the subject, as, on some accounts, secondary sensory qualities also do, b u t - unlike the secondary qualities - they are presented as characterizing the sub- ject. I recognize the fear as my fear, even though it may be caused by God.

Indeed, a fear may be associated with no presented object whatsoever. There are nameless fears. And, there are fears prompted by belief but in the absence of the feared item. I may fear the dragon I believe to be waiting for me in the bushes on a dark night. But there are no dragons, and my dragon- fear does not constitute a presentation of one; it is not even a presentation of an intentional dragon. Or a real dragon could be the cause of my fear: perhaps others have seen it, and rumor of its proximity reaches me. Indeed, the dragon could even be as prominent a cause of my fear as it could be of any sense experience: perhaps surgeons have implanted a transponder in my brain's fear center; radio signals emitted by the dragon trigger the transpon- der though the dragon is nowhere in view. Perhaps I even know that my fear

25

is being caused in this way by the dragon. That still does not constitute my experiencing a presentation of the dragon.

And so it is with the fear - or love - that God causes or prompts me to direct toward Him. Such feelings may be inspired by a theophany or in some other way; but in no case are they themselves constituents of the qual- itative character of a presentation.

That leaves the possibility that God is presented as loving or fearsome. But I know of no way in which an object could be presented to one as having such affective qualities, except by way of being presented also as having some non-affective qualities; and Alston has not explained how this could occur. In view of that, I judge it best to hold that the phenomenal qualities which characterize theophanies include some non-affective ones. Let it then be granted that theophanies do present such qualities, however difficult it may be to identify and convey to others what they are.

2. Can mystical experiences be cross-checked?

But if our descriptive grasp of the content of theophanies is as tenuous as Alston suggests, it becomes an especially critical matter that there be robust means for checking the accuracy of beliefs founded upon them. I shall call such evaluation procedures cross-checking. We must consider how it is pos- sible to cross-check both particular reports of theophany, and the correct- ness of the inferences drawn from them. 'Cross-checking' is an umbrella term: it embraces both the utilization of an overrider system and of more indirect ways to establish credibility; for example, appeal to systemic fea- tures such as self-support. Here we must embark, then, upon an investiga- tion of the second issue which I raised at the outset.

Since SP is to serve as our test case, I shall have to characterize, at least partially, the cross-checking procedures which can be deployed to evaluate both ordinary perceptual claims and scientific hypotheses. I shall then try to identify and characterize a Christian mystical practice, for the purpose of seeing how its confirmation procedures work. Of course, every cognitive practice must have procedures adapted to the peculiarities of its domain and to the nature of our accesss to that domain. Making allowance for this as best we can, the appropriate question to ask is whether the evaluation resources of CMP display a power, richness, and subtlety at least roughly comparable to those available to SE It will emerge that there is a quite general differ- ence between the domains of SP and CMP which hamstrings cross-check- ing in CMP and precludes any parity with SP.

Before I proceed, a word must be said about a certain dialectical feature of the issue before us. One defensive strategy which exercises a perennial

26

attraction for theists is that of tearing down the epistemic credentials of the 'competition' - in this case, science and ordinary sense perception. But in this context, that strategy (with which Alston himself flirts) is bound to backfire. At least, it's bound to backfire unless it can be shown that religious experience enjoys some special and privileged position, vis-i~-vis theologi- cal conclusions, not enjoyed by sense perception vis-&-vis science. And that much Alston isn't prepared to claim on behalf of religious experience.

The defensive strategy in question typically arms itself with the weapons of a general skepticism, and it backfires because the question of the epis- temic status of theological claims cannot be interestingly posed in that con- texc 12 The interesting question - the question theists should want to answer in the affirmative, I take it - is not whether we can know anything about our world, but, granting that we can know the usual sorts of things that we com- monsensically take ourselves to know, whether we can go on to establish the epistemic credentials of some religious creed. After all, if general skep- ticism is the issue, why focus on our knowledge of religious truths? If the task is to refute general skepticism, then, epistemically speaking, establish- ing the credentials of religious beliefs is, if not the least of our worries, also certainly not the most pressing.

Thus the proper way to pose the question - and the way Alston does, in effect, pose it - is to ask whether the epistemic credentials of given reli- gious beliefs are at least any weaker than those of, say, well-accepted scien- tific theories. The task of apologetics here is to address the rather common and powerful feeling that religious claims are indeed significantly worse off than that.

If we grant this dialectical fetaure of the situation, then we must proceed by granting, in this context, the epistemic legitimacy of all those justifica- tory tools standardly employed in scientific reasoning to legitimate scientific conclusions. To call those into question would be to forfeit the game. On the positive side, the theist can of course help him- or herself to these very same reasoning procedures, so long as they can be applied to the justifica- tion of religious claims. For starters, this means that religious perceptual experiences must be accorded some prima facie evidential weight. How much weight remains to be seen; that will depend upon epistemically rele- vant similarities to and differences from ordinary sense perception.

Even if we understood them better, it would be impossible to set out in short order the character and variety of the confirmation procedures available to SE Nevertheless, at the level of generality suitable here, it is possible to identify some important components of SP and to identify the ontological presuppositions which allow us to make sense of their epistemic role. When doubts arise about a scientific hypothesis or sense-perceptual claim, recourse can be had to (at least) the following sorts of strategies: observations can be

27

checked by other observers and can be repeated; a claim can often be tested by other means; competing claims can be tested and disconfirmed. Where non-deductive inference must be used, enumerative induction and abduction are standard strategies. When a claim coheres with other beliefs, it is indi- rectly confirmed by the evidence for those beliefs. 13

And finally, there are strategies to cope with the implications of Duhem's Thesis. These deserve to be singled out for special mention, since they are central to the operation of the SP overrider system. They include the strate- gies already mentioned: specifically, repetition of an observation, independent tests of a claim, and elimination of competitors. But here there is a further epicycle. When a hypothesis H l is challenged because in a crucial experiment it generated an incorrect prediction, that challenge can be deflected by pinning the blame on one or more of the auxiliary hypotheses (call these Al) used in conjunction with H~ to generate the experimental prediction. But that, of course, is not the end of the matter: A l is now a candidate for testing, and defenders of Hj must propose an alternative to A~, call it A*, which when conjoined to H 1, yields the correct observations. A*, can in turn be tested against A v by means of some independent test. That test will of course require invoking further auxiliary assumptions - call them B l - and A* can be defended against disconfinning evidence by blaming the auxiliary auxil- liaries BI.

It might seem as if this game can be repeated ad nauseam, without pro- ducing any significant confirmation or diconfirmation of H v That is indeed a methodological concern, but to raise it is to raise in one of its forms the fundamental problem of induction; ~4 and we have foresworn skepticism. This permits us to say the following, which surely reflects actual scientific practice. Let H~ and H 2 be two competing hypotheses, which are subjected to various sorts of crucial tests in which they make distinctive predictions. Each can be defended against disconfirming evidence by making ad hoc adjustments in auxiliary assumptions, but under the following constraints: (1) the new auxiliaries must be made to cohere t5 with the rest of the belief system, and (2) they must in turn be independently tested against the auxil- iaries they are to replace. This can lead to tests of auxiliary auxiliaries, and so on. As an investigation proceeds, we should judge that, other things being equal, getting things right ahead of time counts in favor of a hypothe- sis, whereas ad hoc adjustment is a demerit. Thus, H v its auxiliaries, auxil- iaries to auxiliaries, etc., acquire a 'track record' which can be compared to that of H 2 and its auxiliaries, etc. The better the track record, the more likely the hypothesis (and the system of beliefs in which it functions).

What I have just done is to characterize the overrider system for SP, but a brief illustration will serve to fix ideas. Suppose ! claim to observe an unusual chromosome structure under the microscope. One way of checking

28

this is to have others look through the microscope; another is to look at the preparation under different sorts of microscopes or scanning devices, or to investigate the material using different sorts of tests altogether, e.g. the chemical procedures for gene sequencing. These are all alternative tests of the leading claim. Alternatively, one might double-check the staining tech- nique I used or the operation of the microscope. That would be, in effect, to subject some of my auxiliary hypotheses to testing.

Now there is, I want to suggest, a single, fundamental presupposition that guides, explains, and justifies all these strategies. It is a presupposition about the causal structure of the world, and about our place as perceivers within that structure. We may state this presupposition as a conjunction of three theses. (1) Events - at least events which are of significance to science and sense perception - are not causally isolated; they have multiple causes and/or effects. (2) Just as matter is composed of parts which can combine in myriad ways, so causal interactions have a compositional structure: forces can combine in myriad ways (though not in just any way) to produce events. (3) Any case in which we observe, detect, or measure some item distinct from ourselves necessarily involves the creation of a causal link between features of that item and our sense experience, which has at least the charac- teristic that the content of the experience is sensitive to changes in the char- acter of that item. ~6

Duhem's Thesis is simply a reflection of theses (2) and (3). The entities and causal processes which scientific theory postulates do not operate in isolation; and any measurement procedure will involve a causal chain whose events are linked through the operation (or absence) of various forces gov- erned by various laws: hence the relevance of auxiliary assumptions. They provide the theory of the measurement process (as well as supplying initial conditions).

I am not saying that a necessary condition of our observing something - a cow or a star - is that we have complete or theoretically sophisticated knowledge of the causal processes which mediate our perception of these items. But I do say that our ability to defend empirical claims, to check them, is a direct function of the degree to which we implicitly or explicitly understand, and are able to control, the causal chains which mediate obser- vation. If we are unable to exert control, we need at least to be able to rec- ognize circumstances under which an item can be reliably observed, and to distinguish those from circumstances which are deceptive. Without s o m e

practical conception of the ways in which an item can causally influence us, we have no grounds for justifying the claim that one set of circumstances produces veridical perception, whereas another leads to e r r o r . 17

This conception of perception as involving causal interaction with our en- vironment is thus central to our understanding of the epistemic practices of

29

SP, of how they put us in touch with the world. It also explains the point of the self-support provided by investigations of our sensory and cognitive mechanisms. What those investigations do is just to flesh in our understand- ing of the details of the causal processes which link us to our surroundings; hence they not only can underwrite the alleged reliability of the senses, but they give us a coherent picture of what can go wrong, and why, and how this may be recognized and prevented. In short, they fill in major portions of the SP overrider system.

Now, how do matters stand with respect to cross-checking theophanies? Before we can approach this question, we need to have before us some rea- sonably well-specified example of a mystical practice. And here we confront an initial problem. Recognizing that mystical practices vary from tradition to tradition, Alston narrows his focus to Cht%tian mystical practice.

But to suggest that there is any such thing as the Christian mystical practice is to engage in a fantasy. It is important to remind ourselves that within Christianity there is nothing remotely like a uniform set of attitudes toward, practices connected to, and standards for evaluating, theophanies. Some Chris- tian communities - this varies with both denomination and, significantly, the socioeconomic background of the members of a congregation - are decidedly hostile to, or suspicious of, such experiences. For other groups, such as the Quakers, Shakers, Southern Baptists, Pentecostals, and some anabaptist sects, some form of possession is the very stuff of worship and religious authority. TM

Alston is well aware of the difficulty, 19 and recognizes that he needs to minimize its import. It is important to see why. At issue are Alston's criteria for the rationality of a doxastic practice. 'It is rational', Alston says, 'to engage in any such practice that is socially established, that yields outputs that are free from massive internal and external contradiction, and that demonstrates a significant degree of self-support'. 2~ But ME unfortunately, does yield massively contradictory outputs. One way to soften the implica- tions of this is to show that CMP can be isolated from other, conflicting MP's. This at least reduces internal contradiction, though at the expense of increasing external contradiction. Even more important, perhaps, is the con- sideration that, because of the wild divergence of background beliefs within MP as a whole, there will be no way of generating significant self-support; a suitably restricted CMP stands a better chance in this regard.

On the other hand, rescuing the internal consistency of a practice by excis- ing from it all conflicting elements is to trivialize the claim of consistency. 21 Alston's compromise is to admit certain 'mainstream' denominations, but refuse to declare himself on where the boundaries lie. That is, I think, a hopeless approach to the issue. We can hardly be asked seriously to evalu- ate a doxastic practice when we have no real idea what is included within it and what is not, or why.

30

By quite defensible standards, the mystical practices of snake-handling Pentecostals more closely approach loa possession in Haitian Voodoo than they do the leadings of the Inner Light experienced by a sedate Philadelphia Quaker. Alston may protest that the output beliefs and overrider systems of the Quaker more closely match those of the Pentecostal than do those of the Voodooist. But this will be pretty thin gruel on which to nourish the thesis of Christian solidarity. The Quaker may reject the doctrines of original sin and the Trinity; she may deny the divine sonship of Jesus; she may have no use for the millennafianism of Pentecostals, scoff at their Biblical literalism, and be horrified by their cruel treatment of snakes. 22 And she will unques- tionably deplore their moral standards. Are then the mystical practices of Quakers and Pentecostals to be excluded from the purview of CMP? On what grounds? Certainly theophanies of YHWH are far more consistently sought and achieved by Quakers and Pentecostals than by most of those belonging to the Christian denominations Alston mentions; beyond that, their experiences are subjected with much greater regularity to communal evalu- ation, and have a more significant influence upon the life of the congrega- tion. If anything, Pentecostals and Quakers should be ranked among the experts at CMP.

Faced with this difficulty of diversity, I shall adopt a fairly radical strategy, one which places as much advantage as possible on Alston's side: I shall examine the doxastic evaluation practices of just one important Christian mystic, fleshing that out with Alston's own list of criteria. For the purpose at hand, there is perhaps no more suitable choice than Teresa of Avila, not only because she is a great mystic who lived in one of the great periods of Catholic mysticism, but because she wrestled so ardently and persistently with the ques- tion of veridicality, and has left us a detailed and powerful record of her strug- gles and conclusions. We can safely assume, moreover, that Teresa's criteria for the genuineness of a theophany became institutionalized at least within the Discalced Carmelite order which she founded. And in any case, Teresa is a favorite among contemporary philosophers who discuss Christian mysticism.

Teresa distinguishes three sources of what she sometimes calls 'locutions': God, the imagination, and Satan. Her problem is to find criteria which per- mit recognition of these sources. Here is a list of criteria which can be gleaned from the Life (L) and Interior Castle (IC) 23 (I make no claim to completeness): 1. Genuine locutions (i.e., where God is the source) produce an inner cer-

tainty which is immediate and enduring; the others do not (IC, V: 1 w but see V: 3 w 11).

2. In genuine locutions there is a great clarity of words (IC V: 3 w the devil can also achieve this, but not the imagination); and the words are remembered for a long time (IC VI: 3 w

31

3. Genuine locutions are too swift, non-discursive, and involuntary to be inventions of the mind (IC VI: 3 w167 16).

4. Teresa gives elaborate accounts of the affective states which accompany various species of contact with the divine. These often include physical powerlessness (L 18, w and sometimes detachment (L 20, w167

5. Genuine locutions have the 'power of authority' - they effect what they say during the experience (IC VI: 3 w and they are corrorobated by a confessor (IC VI: 3 w and by Scripture (IC VI: 3 w

6. They have certain 'fruits': feelings of peace (IC VI: 3 w renewed energy, and renewed devotion to God (IC VII: 2 w L 20, w167 The devil's machinations, by contrast, leave disquiet, little humility, involve less preparation of the soul for produced effects, and leave no light to the understanding nor strength to the will (IC VI: 3 w167 16, 17; and 5 w 10).

7. Genuine locutions are sometimes confirmed by miracles - e.g. levitation (L 20, w167 and fulfilled prophecy (IC VI: 3 w167 and 9).

To this, we may append Alston's own list of criteria for true vs. false theo- phanies: 24

True False

Intellect 1. Not concerned with useless affairs 2. Discretion

Will 1. Interior peace 2. Trust in God 3. Patience in pains 4. Simplicity, sincerity. 5. Charity that is meek, kindly, self-forgetful

Futile, useless, vain preoccupations Exaggeration, excesses

Perturbation, disquiet Presumption or despair Impatience with trials Duplicity, dissimulation False, bitter, pharisaical zeal

Some preliminary comments are in order. First, I do not believe I have stacked the deck by omitting criteria that will better withstand scrutiny than these. Second, Teresa does not explicitly put forward her levitations as evi- dence for the veridicality of her mystical experiences, though they occur during a certain kind of rapture. Nevertheless, there can be little doubt, I think, that they are intended to function in that way for her audience, espe- cially in view of her allusion to II Cot. 12 (IC VI: 5 w167 Not even such a stout believer as Alston will, I imagine, be willing to credit Teresa's levi- tation claims: in any case, we have, so far as I know, no adequate corrobora- tion of it. The same holds true of theophany-inspired prophecies. Poulain cites a number of these prophecies by Catholic saints which fa i l edy but none which were fulfilled. Yet, miracles and prophecies are - if we can exclude the machinations of Satan even here 26 - the only evidence that would have

32

real power; for they are the only effects for which theism provides the only plausible explanation.

Teresa, however, thinks otherwise. She thinks the effects listed in (1) - (6) (singly or in combination) could only be produced by a divine cause. Satan, for example, can't read our inner minds well enough to produce the certainty described in (1). And the devil would surely not grant the good fruits mentioned in (6). But how can we be so sure of that? What access do we (or Teresa) have to the devil's power? And why wouldn't Satan - master deceiver that he is - see fit on occasion to further his ends through good works? 27

Alston's argument for the confirmatory force of the moral fruits of theo- phany is equally ineffective. His argument is that these effects are just what one might expect if a theophany has divine origin; hence; their occurrence confirms that origin. This is an inverse probability argument, and it fails for two reasons.

First, we must ask whether a theist has the right to help himself to the presumption that God would be likely to grant the observed gifts to His mystics. Even setting aside the uncertainties produced by God's freedom to do as He wills, the answer is that the theist does not. The evils we observe in this world force him to remain deeply agnostic with respect to our under- standing of what God's purposes require. 28 So this probability is unknown: theists can't claim such knowledge here, but disavow it when faced with the problem of evil.

But suppose the probability in question to be high; does that help? It does not. Consider an analogous case. The Transcendental Meditation movement claims to have demonstrated, by scientific methods, that mediation has a whole range of beneficial effects, including improved performance in school and at work, greater orderliness in one's life, and so on. Grant the validity of the correlational studies; why shouldn't we jump to the causal conclu- sion? After all, the Maharishi has a theory that predicts these connections. The trouble is that there is at least one competing explanation for those cor- relations, which the TM studies do nothing to eliminate. People who are attracted to the TM movement are often people whose lives are at loose ends; and induction into the movement is often accompanied by entry into a tightly knit community of peers in which certain expectations, and behav- iors satisfying them, are strongly reinforced. We have a great deal of evi- dence for the power of such reinforcement, and no reason to discount this explanation of the "results" of meditating. But there is an entirely similar explanation of the "results" of theophany, as any investigation of the social context of mysticism would reveal. 29 In short, where theism and an alterna- tive hypothesis equally explain (make probable) the observed fruits, the existence of those fruits cannot change the relative probabilities of those

33

hypotheses. 3~ What is demanded is the sorts of cross-checking investiga- tions which would reveal whether the causal links go back to social causes (say) alone, or ultimately to God. But the possibility of doing that, I shall now show, is just what CMP does not offer.

Alston accuses the critics of CMP of two sins: the sin of using a double standard, and the sin of epistemic imperialism. We commit the first sin when we apply a stronger standard of proof to CMP than we require of some favored doxastic practice, such as SP. We commit the second sin when we insist on holding CMP to a standard which has its home in some favored practice - e.g. SP - but which is inappropriate to CMP. It seems we critics just can't get it right.

Let's see whether that's so with respect to one supposed commission of the sin of the double standard. Critics of CMP worry that theophanies - especially of the more dramatic sorts - are experienced by only a small number of people, whereas sense experience is available universally. So CMP is a highly restricted practice, not nearly as deeply entrenched as SP: doesn't that weaken its epistemic credentials? Why shouldn't anybody be able to engage in CMP and check the conclusions of the mystics?

Alston has a ready answer. First, CMP itself has an explanation for this: God is unlikely to reveal Himself to those who do not seek Him in the right way. 31 But second, we will see that the critic is applying a double standard here, as soon as we realize that she will not similarly impugn such highly restricted doxastic practices as those engaged in by mathematicians, theoret- ical physicists, or wine-tasters.

But Alston is wrong. Although few of us can become expert wine-tasters or mathematicians, almost all of us can deploy a battery of tests which lie outside those practices, and which can be used to determine the powers of their practitioners. I am not much good at algebraic topology: how do I know that those who do it are? Well, in the first place, they are much faster than I at solving mathematical problems that I can solve. Second, there are an enormous number of mathematical puzzles, the solutions to which are extremely difficult to obtain, but whose correctness is very easy to check once they are given. Some checks are mathematical, others are empirical. 32 As for wine-tasters, we can confirm their claims by sophisticated chemical analyses, by double-blind tests, and so on. Not only can't we do the same for the mystics' claims; the mystics themselves can't do it, as I shall show. There is no double standard here, only good sense. 33

We come now to the central issue: what sorts of cross-checking can prop- erly be required in CMP, why can't it be performed, and what are the conse- quences of that? I am by no means the first to have insisted upon this difficulty: Alston himself discusses four versions of it, those of Martin, Rowe, O'Hear, and Gale. 34 They are guilty, one and all, Alston tells us, of

34

epistemic imperialism - the sin of using SP standards improperly to judge CMP by.

Of these authors, Gale is the one who sees most clearly the underlying source of the difficulty, and is quite explicit in pointing to it as the decisive consideration - namely, that proper cross-checking requires a causal picture linking God with theophanies "in the right way," a picture that CMP doesn't supplyY Surprisingly, in his response to Gale, Alston misses this point, perhaps because Gale makes heavy weather over the analogical character of Alston's argument, and Alston thinks the difficulty can be deflected by renouncing the dependence upon an analogy to SP. I shall press Gale's point by showing that the need for such a causal picture can be demonstrated quite independently of whether the arguments for CMP are mounted by way of analogies to SP; that indeed this requirement is a necessary feature of an)'

doxastic practice that claims to give us information about extra-mental real- ities. Moreover, although Gale thinks the difficulty for CMP is rooted in the non-spatial character of God, I shall show that it can be raised without locat- ing the difficulty so precisely. 36 Futhermore, the lack of a causal picture not only undermines CMP's ability to provide real cross-checks, but also its claims to significant self-support.

What, concretely, does the no-adequate-cross-checks charge against CMP come to? As we've already seen, the criteria to which Teresa's CMP does appeal have little or no epistemic bite. What force they do have derives from inverse-probability arguments which are shaky and can in any case be matched by ones for competing hypotheses. More direct and independent cross-checks aren't available. When St. Teresa is receiving an inner locution, we can't call on St. John of the Cross to contemplate and independently confirm the message Teresa says God is sending. St. John of the Cross- check he's not. Nor is there any other known independent means of 'getting at' the object of Teresa's theophany. Furthermore, there is no recognized way to get ahold of the medium of tranmission of the divine message, to test whether the phone line is properly connected, so to speak.

Alston locates the problem in the fact that God freely chooses when, how, and to whom to communicate, so that we lack the controls and reproducibil- ity relevant to performing these sorts of tests. And he goes on to charge critics with epistemic imperialism, or chauvinism, for insisting upon stan- dards which, while suited to SP, have no proper application within CMR But there's no chauvinism in demanding such tests. If God is elusive in the ways alleged, then genuine tests may be hard to come by; but the consequence is just - unsurprisingly - that CMP can't tell us much, that we can rely on, abou t God . 37

Defenders of ESP have an even more artful version of Alston's move. Faced with the regular disappearance of paranormal phenomena in well-

35

controlled settings and - even more dramatically - in the presence of expe- rienced magicians - ESP devotees argue that the 'vibrations' are very context-sensitive: laboratory environments and magicians kill them off. It may be so; but we have no fight to conclude from this that tests performed in a psychic's favored uncontrolled environment have the proper epistemic credentials. Alston's explanation for the inapplicability of SP-style cross- checking techniques to CMP is less ad hoc than the psychic's. But so what? Why should that help the credibility of CMP?

It is now time to let a well-concealed cat out of the bag. All the parties to this debate - both theists and critics - pretend that we have no idea what the stimulus conditions for theophanies are; that they are sporadic, uncontrol- lable, and follow no predictable pattern of occurrence or content. But with respect to many religious traditions, including many Christian ones, this is a fairly wild exaggeration.

In many cultures, theophanies - or their religious analogues - are highly stereotyped in both content and occasions of occurrence. When a young Amerindian embarks upon a vision quest, we can, knowing his tribal and clan membership, come to fairly definite conclusions about the species of the spirit-animal he will encounter, and perhaps also when he will encounter it. Similar claims can be made across a wide range of contexts. 38 Closer to home, Sargant 39 reports that "excitement' at a snake-handling Pentecostal service (and, presumably the trance-induction which marks possession by the Holy Spirit) was controlled by the preacher's hand-clapping rate. Student observers were able to manipulate the phenomenon by 'taking over' the hand-clapping. 4~ The fact is that we know a fair bit - relative to our under- standing of human psychological states generally - about the mundane cir- cumstances which favor possession states.

No: The trouble lies elsewhere. However much the mundane parts of the theist's causal story may be accessible to inspection and manipulation, the supra-mundane part of it - the part that is crucial in linking a theophany to God - seems not to be. Unless there is such a link, a theophany is no per- ception of God; and unless there are ways of independently confirming, in principle, that such a link exists, we have no way of distinguishing genuine theophanies from counterfeits. That means the theist must have some grasp of what would be involved in detecting links in a causal chain terminating in God; but we have no such grasp. Worse still, the supra-mundane part of the story has hardly even been told in any detail, beyond such suggestions as that God 'infuses' certain feelings into the mystic, or simply that He causes certain sensory and non-sensory perceptual states. The fact that this story hasn't been told is one obvious reason why cross-checks are not in the offing; but it will be useful to consider why telling (and confirming) any such story is so hard.

36

Alston suggests that the problem lies largely in the fact that God, a free agent whose mind we can ill comprehend, does not conform to any pre- dictable pattern in the granting of His favors; and that certainly, we can't subject Him to experimental control. But even if that were so - and I 've suggested that predictability and control vary - it would hardly be decisive, though undoubtedly it would make empirical investigation more difficult. After all, we have learned a great deal about supernovae, even though these explosions are rare, uncontrollable, unpredictable, and (in their initial stages) fleeting.

But all this largely misses the boat. However difficult it may be for us to penetrate God's decision-making process (if one can even speak of such a thing), we must think of God as initiating the causal chain that produces a veridical theophany by means of some divine act. If the causal chain can't be traced back even to such an act, then there is no basis for confidence in MP. It is this - the need to establish suitable causal connections between object and subject - that is, necessarily, a sine qua non of any doxastic prac- tice that claims to yield justified perceptual beliefs about extramental entities. This requirement is not one that is artificially imposed by SP chauvinists or imperialists; it is simply a corollary of the causal condition on perception. 4~

A beautiful illustration of this point is contained in Jean Perrin's seminal monograph, Brownian Movement and Molecular Reality, 42 which was deci- sive in convincing the physics community of the atomic structure of matter. Perrin approached the problem of determining Avagadro's number through an elegant series of investigations of Brownian motion. But Perrin summarizes no fewer than 15 independent methods - 12 not involving Brownian motion at all - which yield (more or less precise) values for Avogadro's number, all in striking agreement with one another. In this striking convergence, which can hardly be a matter of chance, Nature provides eloquent testimony that all these measurements are putting us in touch with one and the same underlying reality. Moreover, within each of his own methods, where doubts arise as to the accuracy of a given intermediate result, Perrin has recourse to independent determinations; 43 and, where questions arise over how a result should be inter- preted, to independent procedures for analyzing the measurement process itseff. All these strategies are possible because events - in the physical world at least - have both multiple possible causes and multiple possible effects. Multiple effects permit multiple independent lines of measurement; multiple causes permit (often) multiple means of production and control.

The trouble with theophanies seems to be, briefly, that we have no such multiple lines of detection by means to which to 'triangulate' the alleged divine cause; or at least none that don't converge (as in the case of mass vis- itations of the Holy Spirit upon Pentecostals) on some mundane segment of the causal story. 44

37

How might one hope to capture the causal connections between divine acts and human experience? It might help to consider the simplest possible case. Suppose that a divine willing just directly makes it the case that Teresa experiences a theophany. The act is the proximate cause of the experience, or, if you prefer, of the neurological substrate of the experience, without further mediation. We might call this the 'fiat lux' theory of divine action. In order to establish a causal connection, we would at least have to establish some regularity between the one type of event and the other. But how do we observe events of the former type? Relying on Teresa is no help here. Obviously, we must appeal to some independent experience that co-varies with Teresa's, and which is such that the best explanation for that covariance is that it is produced by a causal fork at whose apex is a divine act, not some mundane event. I see no reason in principle why things couldn't have turned out that way, but they have notY

Perhaps God is an elusive quarry because He wishes to be; many liberal theologians even take great comfort in that supposition. Perhaps God achieves this, in part, by insuring that His acts have singular, not multiple proximate effects. 46 Perhaps so, but then so much the worse for CMP. Its overrider system is thereby undermined. 47

It may be helpful to summarize the argument of this section by setting it out more formally. It goes as follows:

(1) A perceptual experience E is a veridical experience of object O only if O plays the right solt of causal role in the production of E. (2) If x is a necessary condition for y, and x may, for all one knows, be false, then one doesn't know that y. (3) Therefore, the claim that E is a veridical experience of O can only be established (or defended) by showing that O played the right sort of causal role in the production of E. (4) The only way (if there is any) to confirm that O played that sort of role is to obtain independent evidence for a causal chain (of the right sort) linking O to E. (5) The only way independently to confirm the existence of such a causal chain is to rely upon the fact that causes have (or can be so manipulated as to have) multiple effects; it is only via these effects that independent observations of the events in a causal chain can be obtained. (6) A perceptual experience E is a veridical perception of God only if God causes E in the right way. (7) So the claim that E is a veridical experience of God can only be con- firmed by means of independent observations of the causal chain linking God to E, and hence must rely upon multiple effects of the divine action. 4s

I take (1) to be a necessary truth. I do not think it is an analytic truth, but I do take it to be (at least) metaphysically necessary. For present purposes, it

38

will not be necessary to concern ourselves with criteria for settling what the right sort of causal connection between O and E must be, since our question is whether any sort of reasonably direct causal connection between God and mystical experiences can be established.

Alston agrees that (1) is at least true. (2) is also a necessary truth. By 'independent evidence' in (4) and (5), I mean the sort of evidence which Perrin amassed by different procedures for Avagadro's number. (4) and (5) I take to be (nearly) self-evident. If there is doubt about the causal role of O in the production of E, it would be merely circular to appeal to E as demon- strating the presence of O. Where O is distinct from E itself, there is no question of obtaining a priori evidence for the presence of O. The remaining alternative is to "triangulate" by looking for independent effects of O, and of intermediate events in the causal chain linking it to E, and arguing that the presence of O best explains the concilience of those effects with E and with each other.

This argument is quite general. It applies, as I see it, to any cognitive prac- tice whatever which relies upon 'input' from perceptual experience, and which generates inferences to beliefs concerning matters external to ourselves.

3. Is mystical practice self-supporting?

The last requirement that Alston places upon a doxastic practice is that it must generate significant self-support. In the case of SP, this is supposed to come in the form of empirical investigations which show that our senses are reliable. But coming to CMP, though he concentrates upon a particular case of alleged self-support, Alston immediately broadens the notion of self- support to include coherence of any kind among the beliefs generated by a practice. This should come as no surprise, given that an immediate corollary of CMP's failure to supply a testable causal account of theophanies is that it flunks the first test.

How well does CMP do on a general coherence account of self-support? In particular, how well do the perceptual beliefs generated within CMP con- tribute to over-all coherence of the 'the' Christian belief-system? Certainly, if we make allowances for denominational differences, Alston can point to a broad range of agreement, and conformity to central Christian doctrines, among CMP perceptual beliefs. But this coherence is bought too cheaply.

A fair amount of consistency should not be too surprising, whether God has a hand in theophany or not, as the case of Transcendental Meditators shows. On the other hand, divergent experiences and beliefs can always be discounted because they do not conform to accepted doctrines (see Teresan criterion number 5).

39

But wait a minute: isn't this the sin of using a double standard? After all, SP admits a certain amount of inconsistency, and often discounts perceptual beliefs which conflict with well-entrenched doctrine. Indeed; but in most cases, SP can depend on its overfider system to supply independently test- able justifications for rejecting anomalies. CMP also appeals to its overrider system: but unfortunately that system can't carry the epistemic burden required of it. So there's no double standard here.

Alston would like to focus attention upon an aspect of the self-support of CMP that invokes its predicative p o w e r - specifically, upon fulfillment of the divine promise that, through faith and sincere struggle, a Christian will undergo sanctification, that is, achieve an eternal loving communion with God. Favorable evaluation of the predictive success of CMP in this regard is supposed to contribute to the self-support of CMP because it is only from within Christian practice that progress on the road to sanctification can be assessed.

With all due respect, I would suggest that this last claim requires an argu- ment. Sincerity, purity of heart, moral uprightness and the like - these are universal human possibilities; the ability to judge them in ourselves and others is something we imbibe with our mother's milk. And the supra-mundane portion of the promise - once again - no one has access to.

Alston loads the dice even futher by suggesting the writings of recog- nized saints as the source of our best evidence for the sanctifying power of proper Christian worship and mystical experience. That's a biased sample if there ever was one: to evaluate the divine promise, we need to examine not only the success stories, but the failures: devout Christians who did not achieve the hoped-for fruits of their faith.

Perhaps an underlying worry of Alston's is the dismaying recognition that Christians, on the whole, cannot point to greater moral or spiritual accom- plishments than can members of the other religious traditions. That fact throws into relief the weakness of this line of self-support. To evaluate pre- dictive success, we first need to know the content of the promise that is to be fulfilled. What ate the conditions that must be met for sanctification to occur? Or even: are they easy - such that most sincere Christians can and do meet them - or very hard? Unfortunately, Scripture does not speak with one voice on this question. 49 Having somehow settled it, we must then balance fulfilled promises against unfulfilled ones. 5~

I have been arguing that, with respect both to the CMP underminer system that supports the reliability of Christian theophanies and to the strength of CMP's self-support, the critical question is whether CMP can supply a test- able causal account of how God influences human experience. Unlike Gale, I am not inferring from God's non-spatiality that such an account could not be given, 51 but I am insisting that an account must be given before CMP can

40

be taken seriously. To some extent, o f course, a similar burden falls on the

shoulders o f those w h o deny supernatural causes. The strength o f inverse

probabi l i ty a rguments for the ism as the best explanat ion o f theophanies is

mos t persuas ive ly undercut by showing that there are equal ly good, or

better, explanat ions that make no supernatural appeal. Because theophanies

do not occur in ent i re ly r a n d o m ways , there is prima facie reason to think

that testable naturalistic explanat ions should be as open to d i scovery and

invest igat ion as are explanat ions o f h u m a n p h e n o m e n a generally. Indeed,

there are such explanat ions , and e lsewhere I shall show that they have con-

s iderably greater power than any supernatural is t ic explanat ion. 52

Notes

1. Roughly similar, but simpler, arguments can be found in C.D. Broad, 'Arguments for the Existence of God, II,' The Journal of Theological Studies 40 (1939): 157-167; Richard Swinburne, The Existence of God (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979), Chapter 13; John Hick, 'Mystical experiences as cognition,' in Harold Coward and Terence Penelhum (eds.), Mystics and Scholars: The Calgary CoJ~erence on Mysticism, 1976 (Waterloo, Ont.: Wilfrid Laurier University Press, 1977); Gary Gutting, Religious Belief and Religious Skepticism (Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press, 1982); and William Wainwright, Mysticism (Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press, 1981). The similarities of Alston's strategies to those of Wainwright are especially strong, and much of what I shall have to say applies to his arguments as well. In 'The evidential value of religious experience', International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 16 (1984): 189-202, Ralph W. Clark allows that religious experiences provide no prima facie justification for perceptual religious beliefs based on them, but maintains that they do provide such justification so long as no naturalistic explanation of their occurrence can compete with a religious one. Here I shall be supporting Clark's first claim; in Evan Fales, 'Scientific explanations of mystical experience, Parts 1 and II', Religious Studies (forthcoming in Sept. and Dec. 1996), I will show that Clark, Alston, and others are mis- taken with respect to the second claim.

2. What these are will be made explicit in due course. See Alston, Perceiving God: The Epistemology of Religious Experience (hereafter abbreviated as PG) (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1991), pp. 223-4.

3. There are other troubles as well, but I shall discuss them elsewhere: see Fales, Ibid. 4. Alston, PG, p. 20. 5. Alston calls the first class of defeaters rebutters, and the second class underminers. 6. See Alston, PG, p. 209. 7. It would be circular, as Alston recognizes, to consider this conclusion a demonstration of

that reliability. 8. Alston further distinguishes indirect perception from indirect perceptual recognition

(where one recognizes the presence of something by recognizing some effect of it), as when I recognize that a plane is flying overhead by seeing only its contrail.

9. This rules out those mystical experiences which, if correctly so described, are said to involve a mystical union with God (or with everything) so intimate that all distinctions whatever are obliterated.

41

10. Possibly he does not make this point because, although he speaks ot' the qualities in question as phenomenal characteristics and even refers to them as qualia, he evidently means them to be the qualities the presented object is presented as having, without prej- udice to whether this makes those qualities purely subjective qualities of purely subjec- tive objects, i.e. of sense data, or objective qualities of extramental objects.

11. Alston overstates the point. In some Christian communities, and in many non-Christian ones, theophanies are induced in highly regularized, predictable, and communally shared ways, and there is a high degree of consensus as to content. But I shall follow Alston's lead for the moment.

12. That isn't quite how Alston sizes up the situation. His strategy is first to deploy the weapons of skepticism to argue that our ordinary sense-perceptual practices (SP) can't be non-circularly justified (in a purely epistemic sense); to then construct a quasi-prag- matic justification for SE and finally to argue that, using the same standards which vin- dicate SP, we can put MP on a roughly equal footing. Thus, Alston claims to have rebutted the charge that SP, unlike ME can noncircularly be given a clean epistemic bill of health. I do not think that Alston's quasi-pragmatic approach to vindicating SP and MP can possibly succeed, but that's not my topic here: see Norman Kretzmann, 'St. Teresa, William Alston, and the Broadminded Atheist', Journal of Philosophical Research 20 (1995): 45-66 for a penetrating discussion of how Alston fails, and Alston, 'Reply to Critics', Journal of Philosophical Research 20 (1995): 67-81 for a reply. Like Kretzmann, I do not think that Alston's level-distinction between knowing and knowing that one knows cuts the ice required of it. I am not pursuing that theme here; tbr present pur- poses, what matters is simply this: however SP is ultimately to be vindicated, the issue for Alston effectively becomes one of granting that SP is on a secure footing, and then undertaking to establish a rough parity, in the sanle general terms, for ME

13. My own view is that these strategies are best understood within a Bayesian framework. 14. In effect, this is the problem of radical underdetermination of theory by data. 15. Coherence is (at least) a matter of logical consistency and probabilistic coherence - that

is, of each of the propositions of the revised belief system having a sufficiently high probability relative to the conjunction of the remaining propositions.

16. 1 do not regard (3) to be analytically true. The modality here is that of either causal or metaphysical necessity.

17. Even an understanding which is rudimentary and implicit can play a significant role here. In the case of ordinary perceptual judgments, our knowledge of suitable conditions for observation, and of how to compensate for non-optimal conditions, is acquired through the myriad daily opportunities to compare our judgments with those of others, to compare the verdicts of different sensory modalities, and to compare judgments under varying circumstances. In this way we gain mastery over at least a larger number of patterns of covariation which signal causal dependencies. The same applies to more sophisticated measurements. When Galileo, whose understanding of optics was rudi- mentary, wanted to check the reliability of his telescopes, he trained them upon terres- trial objects which could also be observed near at hand. But then he was vulnerable to the charge - which was made - that the observation of celestinal bodies was a very dif- ferent matter from observation of terrestrial ones, so that reliability in the one domain could not be taken to underwrite reliability in the other. The complexity and precision of the overrider system for SP is nicely displayed in Ian Hacking, 'Do we see through a microscope?', Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 62 (1981): 305-322 and Jean Perrin, Brownian Movement and Molecular Reali~. (London: Taylor and Francis, trans. E Soddy, 1910).

42

18. It is by no means easy to bring order to all this variety; since there are divergences of belief and practice even within sects, and significant transformations over time, it would in many cases be highly misleading to pretend that there is a stable MP that can be asso- ciated even with a single sect over significant stretches of time.

19. See Alston PG, pp. 192-4. 20. Alston PG, p. 184; also Chapter 4. 21. Initially in PG, Alston makes it appear to be a matter of indifference whether contradic-

tions within MP are of an interpractice or intrapratice sort - hence not crucial how we split MP into more specific practices. It turns out, however, that where the boundaries between practices are drawn matters a great deal after all (see pp. 271-2). Interpractise conflicts are claimed to cut less ice because distinct practices do not share an overrider system. By segregating CMP from other MP's, Alston hopes to isolate it, to some extent, from conflicts with other rivals. Without this isolation from rival MP's, Alston's argu- ment for the rationality of engaging in CMP would founder. For a criticism of this strat- egy, see J. L. Schellenbe~, 'Religious experience and religious diversity: A reply to Alston', Religious Studies 30 (1994): 151-159.

Alston thinks that the failure of two doxastic practices to share the same overrider system (because they do not share the same system of background beliefs) somehow relieves their participants of the responsibility to resolve contradictions, without making continued acceptance of a practice irrational. But why can't conflicts between back- ground beliefs also be put on the table for evaluation? Alston seems here to be flirting with epistemic relativism. Once it is recognized that the central issue is the tracing of causal chains, the weakness of Alston's argument becomes apparent. The background beliefs of different doxastic practices may incorporate radically different views as to what causes what; but so long as they share some general conception of what it is for one event to cause another, there is no reason here to suppose that differing systems are incommensurable or incomparable.

22. Thomas Burton gives an excellent introduction to the practices of the Pentecostal- Holiness churches in his Serpent-Handling Believers (Knoxville, TN: University of Tennessee Press, 1993). For a vivid and sometimes poignant evocation of the lives of the snake-handlers, see Dennis Covington, Salvation on Sand Mountain: Snake-Handling and Redemption in Southern Appalachia (New York: Addison Wesley, 1995).

23. My source is The Book of Her Life and The Interior Castle, both in The Collected Works of St. Teresa of Avila, trans. Kieran Kavanangh and Otilio Rodriguez (Washington, DC: ICS Publications, 1976).

24. Alston PG, p. 203. 25. Poulain, writing with the Papal imprimatur, clearly displays the traditional ambivalence

of the Catholic Church towards its mystics. See Anton Poulain, The Graces of Interior Prayer (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, trans. Leonora Yorke Smith and Jean Vincent Bainvel, 1950 [1910]). Poulain recognizes (Chapter XX) that failed prophecy presents a theological problem: the mystics in question are, after all, canonized. On the other hand, Poulain is eager to demonstrate that ecstasy is not an infallible source of information. Yet, he does take the levitations to be genuine. Teresa herself exhibits an awareness that the question of prophetic infallibility must be carefully negotiated (IC VI: 3 w

26. Poulain Ibid., p. 340 does report that some unspecified prophecies of Magdalen of the Cross were fulfilled. But these were Satan-inspired and designed to convince others of her sanctity. Magdalen's alleged levitations are also claimed to have been the work of Satan. (Poulain 'knows' this because Magdalen, at the near approach of death, confessed it. But she recovered and regretted having clone so. Fuller accounts can be found in

43

Henry Charles Lea, A History of the Inquisition in Spain (New York: MacMillan, 1992 [1907]), volume iv, pp. 82-3; Lea, Chapters from the Religious Histol 3, of Spain (New York: Burt Franklin, 1967 [1890]), pp. 330-36, and Stephen Clissold, Saint Teresa of Avila (London: Sheldon Press, 1979), pp. 4 6 - 7 and 130. According to Lea, Magdalen fell seriously ill, and, upon being told by her physician that death was immanent, she confessed and requested exorcism. She was subsequently handed over to the Inquisition, which treated her leniently by confining her to a prison call for the rest of her life. I am not equipped to form any independent judgment of the accuracy of these accounts of the circumstances of Magdalen's confession; in view of her immense popularity and the willingness of the Inquisition to resort to deception and torture (for which see Lea, A History of the Inquisition of Spain, iii), it might reasonably be wondered whether Magdalen confessed before or after falling into the hands of the Inquisition. Prior to her downfall, Magdalen was a very influential woman, both in secular and in ecclesiastical circles; more- over, Teresa adopted the Rule of the Poor Clares for her own foundation of St. Joseph's in Avila. Teresa, who was 28 years younger than Magdalen and began her career as a mystic some eight years after the latter's conderm~ation, was constantly reminded of Magdalen's fate and occasionally explicitly compared to her.)

27. As God evidently furthers His by sometimes permitting evil. Jesus is said to offer the same strange argument against the accusation that he is performing the work of the devil - see Mt. 12: 22-32; parallels at Mk. 3: 22-30, Lk. 11: 14-23. See also end- note 25.

28. That is so even on the there-is-no-best-possible-world solution to the problem of evil; for on that solution, what right have we to assign a high probability to God's creating a world in which all and only genuine theophanies produce these fruits'? Alston seems to share this agnosticism elsewhere: see PG, p. 219.

29. I shall show this in some detail in Fales, Ibid. 30. This is a formal consequence of Bayes' Theorem. 31. This claim has no better credentials than the one about the likely effects of genuine theo-

phany. 32. We can compare the performance of an airplane designed by a good mathematician/

physicist with one designed by a hospital orderly. 33. Suppose you had no such external ways of checking the reputed abilities of mathemati-

cians or winetasters; suppose each group insisted upon being accountable only to criteria internal to their practice and accessible only to the 'experts'. By what means then could you judge the plausibility of their knowledge claims? Simply relying upon their testi- mony would not distinguish knowledge from delusion. But it is a fantasy to suppose that our cognitive practices are ever to that extent isolated from one another. Still, it might be objected that we don't demand such external checks on SE But there is a reason for this. SP is not a narrow practice, but the broadest empirical practice we have. To make the demand here is to raise the specter of skepticism; but obviously, if there were indepen- dent standards against which we could check SE we'd be foolish not to do so. The present point has to do, however, with relatively narrow practices founded upon (alleged) special perceptual skills or faculties. It would, e.g., be simply mad to take at her word the self-proclaimed clairvoyant who purported to be able to 'see' events in the distant past for which there was no independent historical evidence, save the testimony of other clairvoyants who were in communication with the first.

34. See C. B. Martin, Religious Beliefs (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1959); William L. Rowe, "Religious experience and the principle of credulity'; hzternational JoutTzal for the Philosophy of Religion 13 (1982): 85-92; Anthony O'Hear, Experience,

44

Explanation, and Faith (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1984), and Richard Gale, On the Nature and Existence of God (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991).

35. O'Hear Ibid. also frames the issue this way - see pp. 32-33. 36. In his most recent discussion of Alston's book, Gale himself reverts to this issue, this

time generalizing by allowing the theist to individuate God along any "dimensions' the theist might care to specify. (See Richard Gale, "Why Alston's mystical doxastic practice is subjective', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54 (1994): 869-875.) Alston, changing the issue to identification, replies that there's no reason to think that one can't, with the help of background beliefs, perceptually identify God. (Alston, on the other hand, has done nothing to show how one can produce such a perceptual identification.) Furthermore, Gale has supposedly not shown why the general tests he takes to be essen- tial to any perceptual cognition (the cross-checking repertoire) are required of the mystic. In all this, I am arguing that the fimdamental issue is whether there is a suitable causal connection between God and putative theophanies, and whether anyone can provide evi- dence of that fact. Without such a connection, the theophany is not a verdical one.

In his recent paper, 'Truth-warranted manifestation beliefs', Faith and Philosophy 11 (1995): 436-2451, John Zeis has taken a different tack, reopening the issue whether some mystical experiences are self-authenticating, for the mystic at least. Relying upon the claims of John of the Cross and Teresa that a certain type of intellectual vision can't be produced by the devil, Zeis argues they couldn't be, in that case, delusions of any sort. Supposedly, the mystic can recognize the fact that these experiences can only be produced by God, and not by the devil, in something like the way Descartes is able to recognize that an evil demon can't deceive him about his own existence. But this strat- egy - besides being unduly naive about the nature of our information about such visions (Zeis claims, e.g., to have knowledge of the mental states of Abraham) - is hopeless. In order to tighten the analogy to the Cartesian cog#o, Zeis speculates that because the Holy Ghost 'dwells within' the mystic, the object of the mystic's vision is not external to the mystic; yet he admits that the vision must be caused by God. Further, he admits that subjectively indistinguishable visions may be either veridical or not; they are warranted only when true. That sounds like externalism - a far cry from the Cartesian project. Warrant in that sense is not evidence, as I am using the term.

37. Gale calls Alston's claim to the contrary 'Alston's fallacy'. 38. A similar myth invests miracles with uniqueness, irreproducibility, and unpredictability.

In fact, in many cultures, certain miracles are the regular - and predictable - stock in trade of particular religious ceremonies. In Phoenicia, just a few miles north of Cana during the first century, water was regularly changed into wine by the priests presiding over the annual Bacchus mysteries.

39. See Williams Sargant, The Mind Possessed: A Physiology of Possession, Mysticism, and Faith Healing (New York: J. B. Lipincott, 1974), pp. 183-4.

40. Possibly Alston would disqualify these supposed Holy Spirit possessions on just those grounds. But then why shouldn't Teresa's theophanies (or a Quaker's) be disqualified on the grounds that she used techniques of contemplation and prayer? In neither instance is theophany guaranteed; but in both cases, the probability of occurrence is significantly enhanced. It must be added that Teresa is actually quite skeptical about the efficacy of meditative techniques in this connection, and tends to emphasize the unexpected - even unwanted - 'breaking in' of the divine. But others - e.g. Osuna and St. John of the Cross - are clearly more technique-minded.

41. I am not committing myself here to a causal theory of perception, understood as an analysis of what it means to say that S perceives X. I am committing myself to the view

45

that a causal connection is a necessary component of any state of affairs in which S per- ceives an extra-mental object X, a commitment backed by the strong intuitive appeal of certain counterfactuals. Alston, it appears, would agree - see PG, e.g.p. 230.

42. Jean Perrin, Ibid. 43. Thus, Perrin employs two methods to measure the density of the gamboge spheres he

used to observe Brownian motion, and three methods of determining precisely their diameters.

44. The force of this does not, once again, rely on the disanalogy between CMP and SE Examples t'rom SP merely illustrate, in an area where we know well how to operate, the richness and the interwoven texture of the resources built into a genuine underminer system.

45. Gale thinks that spatial localizability is a requirement on events that can be identified as members of a causal sequence. I am not entirely convinced of that. Alston, on the other hand, thinks the problem of independently identifying causes can't be solved in this case: 'Since we are in no position to say what kind of causal contribution is required for objecthood until we have some genuine cases of object perception to work from, one can't even embark on the project of specifying the necessary causal contribution until one recognizes that there arc authentic cases of object perception. And by then game is lost.' (PG, p. 33). Alston is concerned here with the more complex question of what kind of causal connection is required for something to be a perceptual object; but I take it the point applies equally to the problem of establishing simply what kinds of causal connec- tions there ate. If so, Alston is mistaken here. Of course, it can be argued that the trian- gulation methods I 'm proposing ultimately involve circular reasoning (as they would in SP also); but that is the completely general skeptical objection we've agreed to bracket. That Alston is committed to the view that genuine theophany requires divine causation is quite clear (PG, pp. 228-33). A strict externalist could insist that, so long as theopha- nies generate reliably true beliefs, they yield knowledge, even if we know nothing about the mechanisms involved. But Christians do not take theophanies to be reliable in general, or even within CMP; hence the need for an overrider system. One way around the central difficulty would be to hold that perception of the divine does not require God to play any (or any special) causal role in the production of the perceptual experience. That's not Alston's view; and anyone who holds it owes us an account of perception which makes this alternative intelligible.

46. The experience of Pentecostals and many others apparently to the contrary. 47. Alston might reply that establishing the existence of the "right" causal antecedents to a

theophany - i.e., establishing the legitimacy and successful operation of CMP's over- rider system - is a second-order enterprise. It's here that circularity threatens, here that a quasi-pragmatic defense must be mounted. For Alston, it would amount to a level-confu- sion to suppose that theophany-based theistic beliefs for which no doubts arise, or which the overrider system, such as it is, vindicates, are on that account not rationally held. But this reply would be ineffective. Unless the overrider system can be shown to be suited to the job required of it, the second-order defense of a doxastic practice can't succeed, even if it is only of Alston's quasi-pragmatic sort. What I 've shown is that CMP doesn't have a serious overrider system, ff CMP 'works' in the Christian community, the most plausi- ble explanation is that its success doesn't depend on whether or not the beliefs on which it is based are true.

Alternatively-. Alston might read me as demanding that CMP supply an external justification for claims that particular theophanies are divinely caused. And then he will reply - see PG, pp. 226-7 - that this demand isn't one that SP can (non-circularly) meet either. Since I have a~eed to set aside the question of radical skepticism with respect to

46

SP, fairness demands according CMP the same courtesy. But this would be to misread the objection. The demand for a testable account of the divine causal role in theophanies is not an external demand, but one being made - quite properly - as an internal require- ment for adequacy. Just as - once skeptical problems about inductive reasoning are set aside - such accounts can be given and checked within SP, we are asking whether - again granting CMP all the inference patterns we grant SP - there is a basis for cross- checking, prediction and the like. The trouble is that, by and large, CMP just hasn't got causal explanations for abductive reasoning to reason to, or (by Alston's lights) suffi- cient regularities upon which to base predictions.

48. As it stands, this argument is not formulated quite so as to satisfy the criteria for formal validity; I have tried rather to capture the essential steps of the argument.

49. Jesus' yoke is easy - Mt. 11:28-38 - but also very hard; see Mt. 5: 27-28, 6: 25-34, 7: 13-14, 19: 16-23, and cognate passages in Mk. and Lk. for some examples. ! suspect that Mt. 11:30 is a slap at the policies of Reheboam (see 1 Ki. 12) which destroyed the unified monarchy; but this merely reinforces the problem of deciding what the terms are of the promise made to Christians.

50. Particularly difficult for Christians, I should think, are the divine promises given at Is. 6 2 : 8 - 9 and Mt. 16: 27-28. These do not concern mystical experience, but they do have profound significance for the total Christian story.

51. The question arises whether we could, through ordinao' sense perception, see an embod- ied God (cf. Jn. 14: 7-9) . This would require, I think, an account of the embodiment relation which could explain how, through empirical investigation, it would be possible to determine the presence or absence of this relation between God and a given individ- ual. It would further require an account of what would make an action of the embodying individual an action of the embodied God. I do not believe that Christians have adequate answers to these questions either.

52. See Fales, Ibid. I thank Alston for valuable comments on a draft of the present paper.

Address for correspondence: Professor Evan Fales, Department of Philosophy, The University of Iowa, Iowa City, IA 52242, USA Phone: (319) 335 0023; Fax: (319) 353 2322; E-mail: [email protected]