descartes on the power of ideas

Upload: katie-soto

Post on 03-Jun-2018

218 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/11/2019 Descartes on the Power of Ideas

    1/12

    North merican Philosophical Publications

    Descartes on the Power of "Ideas"Author(s): Stephen I. WagnerSource: History of Philosophy Quarterly, Vol. 13, No. 3 (Jul., 1996), pp. 287-297Published by: University of Illinois Presson behalf of North American Philosophical PublicationsStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/27744708.

    Accessed: 24/06/2014 12:02

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    University of Illinois PressandNorth American Philosophical Publicationsare collaborating with JSTOR to

    digitize, preserve and extend access toHistory of Philosophy Quarterly.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:02:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=illinoishttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=napphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/27744708?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/27744708?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=napphttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=illinois
  • 8/11/2019 Descartes on the Power of Ideas

    2/12

    History

    of

    Philosophy

    Quarterly

    Volume

    13,

    Number

    3,

    July

    1996

    DESCARTES ON

    THE

    POWER OF IDEAS

    Stephen

    I.

    Wagner

    Descartes'discussion

    of

    ideas

    in

    Meditation

    III

    is often

    seen as

    the

    most

    problematic

    element

    in

    his

    metaphysical

    project.

    A

    previous

    paper

    in

    this journal offers a reading ofMeditation II which attributes toDescartes

    a

    conception

    of the

    mind

    as

    an

    active

    power.1

    That

    view

    can

    provide

    a

    range

    of

    clarifications

    to

    Descartes'Meditation

    III

    theory

    of

    ideas.

    This

    paper

    will

    spell

    out the most

    central

    of

    those clarifications.

    Even

    though

    this discussion of

    Descartes'theory

    of

    ideas

    does

    derive

    from

    an

    earlier

    analysis

    ofMeditation

    II,

    it

    need

    not

    be

    seen

    as

    dependent

    on

    the

    validity

    ofthat

    analysis.

    Our initial claims

    about

    the nature

    of

    mind

    can

    be

    considered

    along

    the

    lines

    of

    Descartes'

    own

    approach

    in Part

    VI

    of

    the Discourse

    on

    Method,

    with

    regard

    to the

    suppositions

    he

    employs

    in

    theOptics and theMeteorology. He tells

    us

    inDiscourse VI that he thinks

    he

    can

    deduce

    these

    suppositions

    from his

    primary

    truths,

    but

    that

    in

    his

    presentation

    he would

    simply

    allow the

    causes

    to

    be

    proved

    by

    the

    ef

    fects ?that

    is,

    he

    would

    take the

    explanatory

    force of

    these

    suppositions

    as

    constituting

    such

    proof.

    Our claims about the mind's

    nature

    can

    be

    derived

    from

    the Meditation

    II text.

    But

    the

    present

    discussion

    need

    not

    presuppose

    the

    validity

    ofthat derivation?the results ofthat

    analysis

    may

    also be taken

    as

    suppositions.

    With these

    as

    starting points,

    we

    will

    be

    led

    to

    a

    range

    of

    clarifications

    to

    Descartes'

    discussion

    of ideas

    inMedita

    tion III. These

    effects

    can

    serve

    to

    furnish,

    ifnot

    proof,

    at

    least

    support

    for the

    explanatory

    causes.

    I.

    The Meditation II

    Discoveries

    Our first claim

    is

    that theMeditation

    II

    thinker discovers themind

    to

    be

    an

    active

    power,

    whose

    cognitive

    activity

    consists

    in

    the

    generating

    of

    representations.

    All

    of

    the

    mind's

    cognitive

    acts

    are

    discovered

    to

    involve

    some

    degree

    of

    generative activity?from

    the

    most

    perfect

    exercises ofthat

    power

    in

    generating

    clear

    and distinct

    perceptions,

    to

    the

    less

    perfect

    exercises

    in

    our

    imaginings

    and

    sensings.

    Our

    second claim

    is

    that

    this

    discovery

    is

    achieved

    by recognizing

    that,

    in

    each of

    our

    thoughts,

    the

    power

    affecting

    our

    will is

    a

    reflection

    of the

    mind's

    generative

    power.

    For

    example,

    the

    clear

    and

    distinct

    perception

    of

    the

    piece

    of

    wax

    has

    two

    components?the

    representation

    of

    the

    wax as

    287

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:02:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Descartes on the Power of Ideas

    3/12

    288

    HISTORY

    OF

    PHILOSOPHY

    QUARTERLY

    extended,

    which

    is

    a

    representation

    generated

    by

    the

    intellect,

    and

    the

    power

    compelling

    our

    assent,

    which is a

    representation

    of the mind's

    activity.

    In

    our

    perceptions

    which

    are

    not

    clear

    and

    distinct,

    this

    power

    is

    experienced

    as

    a

    less

    forceful inclination of the will.

    In

    addition

    to

    the

    recognition

    of these individual

    thoughts

    as

    generative

    acts,

    Meditation

    II

    provides

    the

    thinker

    with

    a

    clear and distinct

    perception

    of the

    mind

    itself

    as

    a

    thinking thing.

    This

    perception,

    also

    self-generated,

    is achieved

    by

    consolidating

    the

    spectrum

    of

    representations

    of the mind's

    activity

    into

    a

    single representation,

    which

    consists

    wholly

    of

    a

    power

    affecting

    the meditator's

    will.

    The

    generation

    of this idea of the mind

    explains

    Descartes' claim in the

    Synopsis

    that

    Meditation

    II

    enables

    themeditator

    to

    form

    a

    concept

    of

    the

    soul

    which

    is

    as

    clear

    as

    possible

    and is also

    quite

    distinct from

    every

    concept

    of

    body

    (AT

    VII,

    13;

    CSM

    II,

    9).2

    The natures ofmind and

    body

    are

    presented

    in

    our

    clear and

    distinct

    perceptions

    of

    each.

    The

    clear

    and

    distinct

    perception

    of

    mind

    represents

    it

    as

    a

    generative

    power,

    capable

    of

    operating

    on

    its

    own?as

    such,

    it

    qualifies

    as

    the idea

    of

    a

    substance.

    The

    perception

    of

    body

    includes

    no

    representation

    of

    power

    and

    no

    compelling

    ground

    for

    concluding

    that it exists.

    Finally, these discoveries lead the meditator to an understanding of the

    meanings

    of

    thought

    and existence.

    Thinking

    is

    seen

    to

    signify

    the

    causal

    activity

    of

    generating

    ideas.

    Existing

    is taken

    to

    signify

    an

    exer

    cise

    of

    causal

    power.

    Thus,

    the meditator

    is

    justified

    in

    concluding

    that

    whenever

    he

    thinks,

    he

    exists.

    Given

    these

    claims,

    we can

    turn to

    Descartes' discussion

    of ideas

    in

    Meditation III.

    We

    will look

    first

    at

    the clarifications

    provided

    for

    our

    understanding

    of

    objective

    reality,

    formal

    reality

    and the causal laws.

    We

    will then

    look

    briefly

    at

    the

    impact

    of

    our

    perspective

    on

    material

    falsity

    and the idea ofGod.

    II.

    OBJECTIVE

    REALITY

    AND

    THE

    CAUSAL

    LAWS

    Descartes' discussion of

    ideas

    inMeditation

    III is

    primarily

    in the

    service

    of

    deciding

    whether

    he

    can

    conclude

    to

    the

    existence

    of

    anything

    other

    than

    himself.

    After

    rejecting

    his

    natural

    inclinations

    as

    a

    reliable

    guide

    for

    deciding

    that

    any

    of his

    ideas

    are

    not

    self-generated,

    Descartes

    develops

    another

    way

    of

    proceeding:

    But it

    now occurs

    to

    me

    that there

    is

    another

    way

    of

    investigating

    whether

    some of the things ofwhich I possess ideas exist outside me. In so far as the

    ideas

    are

    simply

    modes of

    thought,

    there is

    no

    recognizable

    inequality

    among

    them:

    they

    all

    appear

    to

    come

    from

    within

    me

    in

    the

    same

    fashion.

    (AT

    VII, 39-40;

    CSM

    II,

    27-28).

    Taking

    an

    idea

    as

    a

    mode

    of

    the

    mind

    is

    taking

    it

    materially ?as

    an

    operation

    of

    the

    intellect,

    as

    the

    Meditations'

    Preface

    tells

    us.

    On

    our

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:02:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Descartes on the Power of Ideas

    4/12

  • 8/11/2019 Descartes on the Power of Ideas

    5/12

    290

    HISTORY

    OF

    PHILOSOPHY

    QUARTERLY

    tion

    from within

    experience.

    And since the

    power

    representing

    the mind

    is the

    power

    to

    generate

    any

    and all ofour

    ideas,

    itwill effectamore forceful

    inclination

    of the will than the

    power

    experienced

    in the

    idea of

    the

    wax.

    Thus,

    the

    idea of the

    mind

    will,

    as

    Descartes

    puts

    it,

    undoubtedly

    be

    seen

    to

    have

    more

    objective reality.

    A

    few clarifications

    are

    in

    order here.

    First,

    this

    reading

    of

    objective

    reality

    leads the meditator

    to

    identify

    reality

    with

    power

    and,

    given

    the

    Meditation

    II

    result,

    to

    equate

    both

    of

    these with

    existence. This three

    fold identification

    is

    supported

    by

    Descartes'

    later

    characterization of

    objective

    reality

    as

    the

    mode

    of

    being

    by

    which

    a

    thing

    exists

    objectively

    in the intellect byway of an idea (ATVII, 41; CSM II, 29). We can note

    too

    that the

    suggestion

    made

    by

    many

    commentators

    that

    objective

    reality

    must

    be

    identified

    with

    possible

    existence

    is

    in

    fact

    appropriate.

    But

    within the

    order

    of

    reasons,

    an

    understanding

    of

    necessary

    existence

    has

    not

    yet

    been

    achieved,

    so

    the

    meditator does

    not

    yet

    have

    the

    resources

    to

    make that finer distinction.

    The statement

    just

    quoted

    leads

    us

    to

    a

    second

    point.

    Descartes

    charac

    terizes

    objective

    reality

    as

    the

    way

    inwhich

    a

    thing

    exists

    in

    the

    intellect,

    and

    this

    might

    seem

    to

    suggest

    that

    it is

    a

    mistake

    to

    explicate

    it

    as a

    power

    affecting the will. But Descartes' comments

    to

    Mersenne

    in

    January

    1641

    are

    helpful

    here:

    I

    claim that

    we

    have ideas

    not

    only

    of all that

    is

    in

    our

    intellect,

    but

    also of

    all

    that

    is in

    the will. For

    we

    cannot will

    anything

    without

    knowing

    that

    we

    will

    it,

    nor

    could

    we

    know this

    except by

    means

    of

    an

    idea.

    . .

    .

    (AT

    III,

    295;

    CSMK

    III,

    1724).

    We

    are

    reminded

    here

    that

    our

    entire discussion

    of

    ideas

    is

    conducted

    from

    a

    self-reflective

    posture.

    From

    this

    posture,

    the inclinations

    of

    the

    will,

    as

    they

    are

    experienced

    in

    our

    thoughts,

    can

    be

    apprehended

    and

    can

    serve

    as

    ideas

    of

    the mind and

    its

    modes.

    A final

    clarification

    is

    provided by

    E.J. Ashworth's criticism of

    Descartes'

    grading

    of

    the

    objective

    realities

    of his ideas:

    .

    . .

    how

    are we

    to

    grade

    the

    reality

    of ideas?

    .

    . .

    Having

    a

    high grade

    of

    reality

    must

    involve

    having

    certain sorts of

    property

    to

    a

    high

    degree, including

    causal

    efficacy

    or

    creative

    power.

    How

    can

    any

    of these be

    assigned

    to

    my

    ideas?5

    Ashworth's

    questions help

    focus

    our

    proposals

    in

    an

    important

    way.

    Our

    ideas

    can

    be

    assigned

    causal

    efficacy

    not

    in

    the

    sense

    that

    they

    them

    selves

    are

    causally

    efficacious;

    rather

    they

    contain

    objective reality

    in

    that

    they

    exhibit

    an

    exercise

    of

    causal

    power.

    The meditator's

    understanding

    that the

    power

    exhibited

    is

    a

    reflection

    of

    the

    mind's

    creative

    activity

    of

    generating

    ideas

    captures

    the

    sense

    in

    which

    objective

    reality

    is

    indeed

    a

    representative

    reality.

    Returning

    to

    the

    text,

    we can

    now

    see

    how Descartes'introduction of

    his

    first

    causal

    principle

    is

    grounded:

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:02:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Descartes on the Power of Ideas

    6/12

    DESCARTES

    ON

    THE

    POWER

    OF

    IDEAS

    291

    Now it is

    manifest

    by

    the natural

    light

    that

    there

    must

    be

    at

    least

    as

    much

    in the efficient and total cause as in the effect of that cause. For

    where,

    I

    ask,

    could the effect

    get

    its

    reality

    from,

    if

    not

    from

    the cause?

    And

    how

    could the

    cause

    give

    it to

    the effect unless

    it

    possessed

    it?

    (AT

    VII,

    40;

    CSM

    II,

    28).

    Our

    perspective

    makes

    plausible

    this claim of

    proportionality

    between

    the

    effect

    and its cause.

    As

    a

    result

    of the

    Meditation

    II

    discoveries,

    the

    meditator

    in

    fact takes

    objective reality

    to

    be

    an

    effect,

    since

    the

    power

    moving

    our

    will

    is

    understood

    to

    be

    a

    reflection of the

    mind's

    generative

    activity.

    Insofar

    as

    it

    is

    such

    a

    reflection,

    the

    claim

    seems

    to

    follow

    easily

    that

    it

    cannot

    exceed

    the

    generative

    power

    itself.

    Thus,

    Descartes'

    princi

    ple seems to be an appropriate candidate for a deliverance of the natural

    light.

    Furthermore,

    we can

    explain

    how Descartes

    can now

    go

    on

    to

    say

    that

    two

    more

    general principles

    follow from

    this

    result:

    It

    follows from this both

    that

    something

    cannot

    arise

    from

    nothing,

    and

    also

    that what

    is

    more

    perfect?that

    is,

    contains

    in

    itself

    more

    reality?cannot

    arise

    from what

    is less

    perfect.

    (AT

    VII,

    40-41;

    CSM

    II,

    28).

    Many analyses

    seem

    to

    reverse

    Descartes'

    movement

    of

    thought

    here,

    suggesting that he derives his first causal principle from these more

    general

    principles.

    But

    our

    analysis

    seems

    to fit

    the

    text

    better,

    since it

    suggests

    that both

    the

    causal

    principle

    and these

    more

    general

    principles

    can

    in

    fact be

    seen

    as

    generalizations developed

    from

    and

    grounded

    in

    the

    Meditation

    II

    experiential

    discovery

    of the

    mind's

    activity

    and

    its effects.

    This

    viewpoint

    accords better

    with

    Descartes'

    claim in

    Second

    Replies

    that

    It is in the nature of

    our

    mind

    to construct

    general

    propositions

    on

    the

    basis

    of

    our

    knowledge

    of

    particular

    ones

    (AT

    VII,

    141;

    CSM

    II,

    100).

    Invoking

    his

    second causal

    principle,

    Descartes

    introduces the

    notion of

    a

    formal

    reality :

    And this

    is

    transparently

    true

    not

    only

    in

    the

    case

    of

    effects which

    possess

    actual

    or

    formal

    reality,

    but

    also

    in

    the

    case

    of

    ideas,

    where

    one

    is

    considering

    only

    objective

    reality.

    .

    .[I]n

    order for

    a

    given

    idea

    to

    contain such

    and

    such

    objective

    reality,

    it

    must

    surely

    derive

    it

    from

    some

    cause

    which

    contains at least

    as

    much

    formal

    reality

    as

    there

    is

    objective

    reality

    in

    the

    idea.

    (AT

    VII,

    41;

    CSM

    II,

    28-29).

    Although

    Descartes

    seems

    to be

    applying

    his

    causal

    principle

    across

    categories ?reasoning

    from

    the

    existence

    of

    a

    certain

    objective

    reality

    in

    his

    ideas

    to

    a

    certain

    degree

    of

    formal

    reality

    in

    their

    causes?our

    perspective

    provides

    a

    corrective.

    As

    we

    have

    seen,

    the

    objective reality

    of

    an

    idea?its

    power

    to

    move

    our

    will?is

    taken

    by

    the

    meditator

    to

    be

    a

    manifestation,

    within the

    realm

    of

    ideas,

    of the mind's

    power

    to

    generate representations.

    The

    formal real

    ity

    to

    which

    the

    power

    affecting

    our

    will

    corresponds

    is

    our

    mind's

    genera

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:02:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Descartes on the Power of Ideas

    7/12

    292

    HISTORY

    OF

    PHILOSOPHY

    QUARTERLY

    tive

    power.

    So

    our

    reading

    shows that Descartes

    is not

    applying

    his causal

    principle

    across

    categories,

    since both formal and

    objective

    realities denote

    causal

    powers.

    He

    is

    simply

    correlating

    the manifestation

    of

    a

    causal

    power

    within

    consciousness

    with the

    power

    itself

    operating

    outside

    the

    realm

    of

    his direct

    awareness.

    Our

    analysis

    shows

    too

    that

    the

    paradigm

    forDescartes'

    introduction

    of

    his

    term

    formal

    reality

    is

    the

    mind,

    insofar

    as

    it

    is

    understood

    to

    be

    a

    generative

    power.

    Thus

    we

    see

    that

    the causal

    relationship

    between

    formal

    and

    objective

    realities

    comes

    first in the order of

    discovery, grounded

    as

    it

    is in the

    Meditation

    II

    discovery

    of

    the

    mind's

    power

    to

    generate

    ideas.

    Our

    understanding

    of formal realities in

    general

    and of formal-to-formal

    causal

    relationships

    must be

    epistemologically

    grounded

    in

    these

    para

    digms.

    We

    should,

    then,

    agree

    with Annette

    Baier,

    who

    has also

    traced

    the

    fundamental

    nature of

    the

    formal-to-objective

    causal

    paradigm

    back

    to

    Meditation

    II

    and

    says:

    If

    the

    causal

    principle

    did

    not

    apply

    to

    objective reality,

    then

    it could

    not

    be

    known

    to

    the meditator

    to

    hold

    good.6

    Within

    the

    order

    of

    reasons,

    the causal

    link

    between

    formal

    and

    objective

    realities

    is

    not

    problematic?it

    is basic.

    Our

    perspective

    also

    helps

    to

    clarify

    Descartes'

    explanation

    of

    objective

    reality

    to

    Caterus

    in First

    Replies

    as

    the

    object's being

    in

    the

    intellect

    in

    the

    way

    in

    which

    its

    objects

    are

    normally

    there

    (AT

    VII,

    102;

    CSM

    II,

    75).

    We must

    take the

    object ?the

    formal

    reality?to

    be

    a

    causal

    power.

    The

    way

    in

    which such

    an

    object

    is

    in

    the intellect

    is

    not

    in

    the form of

    a

    picture

    image.

    Rather

    it

    is

    there

    through

    a

    representation

    of the

    objects's

    causal

    power,

    in

    the form

    of

    the

    power

    affecting

    our

    will.

    Finally,

    our

    perspective

    can

    offer

    a

    clarification

    regarding

    Descartes'

    infamous

    causal

    resemblance

    principle :

    A

    stone,

    for

    example,

    which

    previously

    did

    not

    exist,

    cannot

    begin

    to

    exist

    unless

    it

    is

    produced

    by

    something

    which

    contains,

    either

    formally

    or

    emi

    nently

    everything

    to

    be found

    in

    the

    stone;

    similarly,

    heat

    cannot

    be

    produced

    in

    an

    object

    which

    was

    not

    previously

    hot,

    except by

    something

    of

    at

    least

    the

    same

    order

    of

    perfection

    as

    heat,

    and

    so on.

    But

    it

    is also

    true

    that

    the idea

    of

    heat,

    or

    of

    a

    stone,

    cannot

    exist

    in

    me

    unless it

    is

    put

    there

    by

    some cause

    which

    contains at least

    as

    much

    reality

    as

    I

    conceive

    to

    be

    in

    the

    heat

    or

    in

    the

    stone.

    (AT

    VII,

    41;

    CSM

    II,

    28).

    Descartes'

    principle

    has

    occasioned

    widespread

    discussion

    and

    criticism.

    But

    our

    discussion

    shows

    that the

    meditator has

    been

    led

    to

    understand

    formal and objective realities as powers. Since the meditator is, at this

    point,

    cognizant

    of

    only

    one

    kind

    of

    causal

    power,

    the

    only

    resemblance

    between

    cause

    and effect

    which

    can

    be

    at

    issue here

    concerns

    degrees

    of

    causal

    power.

    From the

    perspective

    which the meditator

    has

    been

    led

    to

    adopt,

    Descartes will be

    seen as

    saying

    simply

    that the

    cause

    must contain

    at

    least

    the

    same

    degree

    of

    power

    as

    is

    contained

    in

    the

    effect.

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:02:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Descartes on the Power of Ideas

    8/12

    DESCARTES

    ON

    THE POWER OF

    IDEAS

    293

    III.

    The Formal Reality

    of

    Ideas?

    A

    further

    clarification

    confronts

    a

    possible

    objection

    to

    our

    analysis,

    Our

    view that

    formal

    reality

    denotes

    generative

    power

    entails that

    ideas

    n

    themselves

    have

    no

    formal

    reality.

    This

    claim, however,

    runs

    counter

    to

    the views

    of

    most

    commentators.

    For

    instance,

    Nicholas

    Jolley

    says:

    While

    laying

    the

    foundations

    for his

    proof

    of the

    existence

    of

    God,

    Descartes

    distinguishes

    between

    the

    'formal' and

    'objective' reality

    of

    ideas:

    ideas

    have

    formal

    (or

    intrinsic)

    reality

    by

    virtue of

    being

    modes

    of

    thought,

    or

    mental

    events;

    and

    they

    have

    objective reality

    by

    virtue

    of their

    object

    or

    repre

    sentational

    content.8

    Vere

    Chappell,

    while

    placing

    his view in the context of his distinction

    between

    ideasm (ideas

    taken

    materially)

    and

    ideas0 (ideas

    taken

    objec

    tively),

    agrees:

    Descartes

    holds that

    there

    are

    different

    modes of

    being

    or

    existence,

    different

    ways

    in

    which

    things

    are.

    Objective

    being

    is

    the mode

    in

    which

    things

    in

    the

    intellect

    characteristically

    exist. This

    sort of

    being

    is contrasted with

    actual

    or

    formal

    being,

    which

    is

    the mode

    in

    which

    things

    outside the intellect

    exist.

    The

    acts

    or

    operations

    of the

    intellect?including

    all

    ideasm?also

    have

    actual

    or

    formal

    being.9

    But

    while

    this

    view

    is

    widely accepted,

    we

    must

    see

    that

    the relevant

    texts

    are

    far from clear

    in

    this

    regard.

    We should

    note, first,

    that Gassendi

    states

    the view

    we are

    questioning

    in his

    objections:

    You do

    in

    fact..

    .distinguish

    between

    objective

    and formal

    reality,

    where

    'formal

    reality,'

    as

    I

    understand

    it,

    applies

    to

    the idea

    itself

    not

    as

    it

    represents

    something

    but

    as an

    entity

    in

    its

    own

    right.

    (AT

    VII, 285;

    CSM

    II,

    199).

    Descartes,

    however,

    does

    not comment

    on

    Gassendi's

    claim,

    passing

    up

    this

    opportunity

    to offer

    us

    explicit

    guidance

    on

    this

    point.

    InMeditation III itself, one passage seems to deny that ideas are formal

    realities:

    . .

    .although

    the

    reality

    which

    I

    am

    considering

    in

    my

    ideas

    is

    merely

    objective

    reality,

    I must

    not

    on

    that

    account

    suppose

    that the

    same

    reality

    need

    not

    exist

    formally

    in

    the

    causes

    of

    my ideas,

    but that

    it is

    enough

    for

    it

    to

    be

    present

    in

    them

    objectively.

    For

    just

    as

    the

    objective

    mode of

    being

    belongs

    to

    ideas

    by

    their

    very

    nature,

    so

    the formal

    mode

    of

    being

    belongs

    to

    the

    causes

    of

    ideas?or

    at least the

    first and

    most

    important ones?by

    their

    very

    nature.

    (AT

    VII,

    41-42;

    CSM

    II,

    29).

    Descartes denies

    here

    that the

    objective

    mode

    of

    being belongs

    to

    the

    causes

    of ideas because their nature is to be formal realities. His claim that the

    objective

    mode of

    being

    belongs

    to

    ideas

    by

    their

    nature

    is

    presented

    in

    a

    parallel

    form?as

    captured

    in his

    just

    as

    (quemadmodum)?suggesting

    that

    we

    should

    deny

    them

    formal

    reality.

    It is

    surely possible

    to

    argue,

    as

    Chappell

    does,

    that

    since Descartes tells

    us

    that

    an

    idea

    can

    be

    taken

    in

    two

    senses,

    the

    formal

    mode of

    being belongs

    to

    ideas taken

    materially.

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:02:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Descartes on the Power of Ideas

    9/12

    294

    HISTORY

    OF

    PHILOSOPHY

    QUARTERLY

    But this

    move

    simply

    creates

    a

    problem,

    which has

    perplexed

    many

    com

    mentators,

    of

    understanding why

    Descartes introduces a different

    term? materially ?rather

    than

    referring

    to

    this

    sense

    as

    an

    idea taken

    formally.

    On

    our

    view,

    this

    problem

    never

    arises.

    Ideas

    taken

    materially

    are

    modes of

    the

    mind,

    but,

    since

    they

    do

    not

    possess

    generative

    power,

    are

    not

    themselves

    formal

    realities.

    In

    one

    other

    passage

    central

    to

    this

    issue,

    Descartes

    describes the

    rela

    tion

    between ideas

    and their

    causes:

    For

    although

    this

    cause

    does

    not

    transfer

    {transfundat)

    any

    of

    its

    actual

    or

    formal

    reality

    to

    my idea,

    it

    should

    not

    on

    that

    account

    be

    supposed

    that

    it

    must be less real. The nature of an idea is such that of itself it requires {exigat)

    no

    formal

    reality

    except

    what

    it

    derives from

    my

    thought

    {praeter

    illam

    quam

    mutuatur

    a

    cogitatione

    mea),

    of which

    it

    is

    a

    mode.

    (AT

    VII,

    41;

    CSM

    II,

    28).

    Descartes'

    claim that the

    cause

    does

    not

    transfer

    any

    of

    its

    formal

    reality

    to the idea

    suggests

    that

    the

    mind,

    in

    its

    causal

    activity,

    does

    not

    provide

    an

    ideam

    with

    any

    formal

    reality.

    What the

    idea does

    derive

    from

    my

    thought

    seems

    to be

    something

    other

    than

    formal

    reality.

    Our

    view

    provides

    an

    answer?the

    idea

    does

    not

    derive

    generative

    power,

    but

    only

    representative

    power,

    in the form of

    a

    power

    affecting

    the will.

    We can conclude, then, that the text does not provide an obstacle to our

    claim that

    ideas

    have

    no

    formal

    reality.

    IV.

    MATERIAL

    FALSITY

    A

    full

    treatment

    of

    the

    issues

    involved

    in

    Descartes'

    concept

    of

    material

    falsity

    is

    beyond

    the

    scope

    of

    our

    discussion.

    It will suffice

    to

    show

    that

    our

    perspective

    is

    helpful

    in

    a

    central

    respect.

    We

    can

    focus

    first

    on

    Descartes'

    description

    of this

    concept:

    For although. . .falsity in the strict sense, or formal falsity, can occur only in

    judgements,

    there

    is

    another kind

    of

    falsity,

    material

    falsity,

    which

    occurs

    in

    ideas,

    when

    they

    represent non-things

    as

    things.

    For

    example,

    the

    ideas

    which

    I

    have of

    heat

    and

    cold contain

    so

    little

    clarity

    and

    distinctness that

    they

    do

    not

    enable

    me

    to

    tell

    whether cold

    is

    merely

    the absence

    of

    heat

    or

    vice

    versa,

    or

    whether both of

    them

    are

    real

    qualities,

    or

    neither

    is.

    And

    since

    there

    can

    be

    no

    ideas

    which

    are

    not

    as

    it

    were

    of

    things,

    if

    it

    is

    true

    that cold

    is

    nothing

    but the

    absence

    of

    heat,

    the idea which

    represents

    it

    to

    me as

    something

    real

    and

    positive

    deserves

    to

    be

    called

    false_(AT

    VII,

    43-44;

    CSM

    II,

    30).

    And

    second,

    we

    need

    to

    see

    Descartes'

    explanation

    of how these

    materially

    false

    ideas

    are

    caused:

    Such ideas

    obviously

    do not

    require

    me to

    posit

    a source distinct from

    myself.

    For

    on

    the

    one

    hand,

    if

    they

    are

    false,

    that

    is,

    represent non-things,

    I know

    by

    the

    natural

    light

    that

    they

    arise

    from

    nothing

    ?

    that

    is,

    they

    are

    in

    me

    only

    because

    of

    a

    deficiency

    and

    lack

    of

    perfection

    in

    my

    nature. If

    on

    the other

    hand

    they

    are

    true,

    then

    since the

    reality

    which

    they

    represent

    is

    so

    extremely

    slight

    that I

    cannot

    even

    distinguish

    it from

    a

    non-thing,

    I

    do

    not

    see

    why

    they

    cannot

    originate

    from

    myself.

    (

    AT

    VII,

    44;

    CSM

    II,

    30).

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:02:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Descartes on the Power of Ideas

    10/12

    DESCARTES

    ON

    THE

    POWER OF

    IDEAS 295

    These

    statements

    indicate,

    as

    a

    number of commentators

    have

    shown,

    that

    we

    must

    distinguish

    the

    representative

    character of Cartesian

    ideas

    from

    their

    objective

    reality. 10

    This conclusion follows

    from the

    fact that

    those

    ideas which arise from

    nothing

    have

    representative

    character

    (since

    all

    ideas

    are

    as it

    were

    of

    things )

    but have

    no

    objective

    reality

    (since

    an

    idea

    can

    have

    no

    more

    objective reality

    than

    there

    is

    formal

    reality

    in its

    cause).

    While

    this result

    has often

    proven

    problematic

    for

    commentators,

    it

    can

    be

    easily

    understood

    from

    our

    perspective.

    Our

    discussion

    has shown

    that

    most

    of

    our

    ideas have two

    components.

    For

    example,

    the clear and

    distinct

    perception

    of

    the

    wax

    consists of

    the

    representation of the

    wax

    as

    extension and the power affecting

    our

    will.

    On

    our

    view,

    the

    latter

    is the

    idea's

    objective

    reality;

    we can

    identify

    the

    former,

    for

    the

    point

    at

    issue,

    as

    its

    representative

    character. The

    objective

    reality

    of

    an

    idea shows

    it

    to

    be the effect

    of

    the

    operation

    of

    some

    causal

    power,

    indicating

    that

    it

    truly

    represents

    a

    thing.

    But

    the

    reality

    con

    tained

    in

    some

    of

    our

    ideas

    is

    so

    slight?they

    exhibit

    so

    little

    power?that

    we

    cannot

    tell

    if

    they

    have

    any

    objective

    reality.

    Nevertheless,

    all

    ideas,

    even

    those which

    seem

    to

    have

    no

    objective reality,

    are

    as

    it

    were

    of

    things

    in

    that

    they

    have

    some

    representative

    character. For

    example,

    even

    the

    idea of cold

    presents

    an

    actual

    sensation,

    as

    Descartes

    tells

    Arnauld,

    and

    thereby provides subject matter for error :

    .

    .

    .my

    only

    reason

    for

    calling

    the idea

    'materially

    false'

    is

    that,

    owing

    to the

    fact that it is obscure and

    confused,

    I

    am

    unable

    to

    judge

    whether

    or

    not

    what

    it

    represents

    to

    me

    is

    something positive

    which

    exists

    outside of

    my

    sensation.

    And hence I

    may

    be led

    to

    judge

    that

    it

    is

    something positive

    though

    in

    fact

    it

    may

    merely

    be

    an

    absence.

    (AT

    VII,

    234;

    CSM

    II,

    164).

    The

    representative

    character

    of the

    idea,

    along

    with

    our

    inability

    to

    discern

    whether

    the

    idea

    has

    any

    objective

    reality,

    may

    lead

    us

    to

    mistakenly

    judge

    that there

    is

    some

    causal

    power?some

    formal

    reality?which generated

    the

    idea.

    But,

    in

    fact,

    it

    may

    arise

    from

    nothing ?that

    is,

    from

    a

    lack

    in

    our

    nature.

    We

    see,

    too,

    that

    this last

    suggestion

    does not

    violate Descartes'

    causal

    principles,

    since

    only

    the

    objective reality

    of

    the

    idea,

    not its

    repre

    sentative

    character,

    has

    been shown

    to

    require

    a

    positive

    cause.

    Our

    perspective

    shows that

    material

    falsity

    is

    indeed

    an

    intrinsic

    feature

    of

    ideas,

    as

    Descartes

    repeatedly

    insisted.

    Some

    ideas

    appear

    to

    not

    exhibit

    any

    power.

    Since

    we

    are

    unable

    to

    discern whether

    they

    do,

    they

    provide

    material for

    making

    false

    judgments

    in

    the

    way

    we

    have

    described.

    V.

    THE

    IDEA

    OF

    GOD

    We

    can

    conclude

    by

    briefly

    offering

    some

    suggestive

    results

    of

    our

    analy

    sis

    regarding

    the

    idea

    of

    God.

    A

    question

    asked,

    but

    left

    unanswered,

    by

    John

    Yolton,

    can

    serve

    as

    our

    focus.

    Referring

    to

    the

    idea

    of

    God,

    he

    says:

    There

    may

    be

    a

    problem

    with this

    particular

    idea.

    .

    .

    .Can

    an

    idea be

    a

    mode

    of

    my

    thought

    but

    not caused

    by

    me?11

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:02:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Descartes on the Power of Ideas

    11/12

    296 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY

    QUARTERLY

    From

    the

    outset,

    the

    Meditation

    III thinker has

    taken

    an

    idea,

    as a

    mode

    of the

    mind,

    to

    signify

    a

    generative

    act. But after

    concluding

    that the idea

    of

    God

    cannot be

    caused

    by

    the

    mind,

    Yolton's

    question

    must be

    confronted.

    The

    discovery

    of this idea

    creates

    a

    tension

    in

    the

    meditator's

    conception

    of

    the mind's

    operations.

    We

    need

    to

    see more

    clearly

    how this tension

    is

    brought

    about,

    by

    recognizing

    the

    unique

    nature

    of this

    idea

    within the

    view we've set out.

    Descartes'indications that this idea

    has infinite

    objective

    reality

    has the

    implication,

    from

    our

    perspective,

    that it exhibits infinite

    power.

    The

    import

    of

    this is

    described

    by

    Descartes

    in

    First

    Replies:

    But if.

    .

    .we

    attend

    to

    the

    immense

    and

    incomprehensible

    power

    that

    is

    contained within the idea of

    God,

    then

    we

    will

    have

    recognized

    that

    this

    power

    is

    so

    exceedingly

    great

    that

    it is

    plainly

    the

    cause

    of his

    continuing

    existence.

    .

    .

    .[W]hen

    we

    perceive

    this,

    we are

    quite

    entitled

    to

    think

    that

    in

    a

    sense

    he

    stands

    in

    the

    same

    relation

    to

    himself

    as

    an

    efficient

    cause

    does

    to

    its

    effect,

    and

    hence that he derives

    his existence from himself

    in

    the

    positive

    sense.

    (AT

    VII,

    110-111;

    CSM

    II,

    79-80).

    From

    our

    perspective,

    Descartes'

    claim has

    two

    epistemological

    conse

    quences.

    First,

    the

    immensity

    of the

    objective

    reality

    of the idea

    of

    God?the

    immensity

    of the

    power

    affecting

    ourwill?seems to eliminate the need to

    posit

    an

    efficient

    cause

    outside

    of

    itself.

    It

    can

    only

    do

    so

    if

    the

    power

    shows

    itself

    to be self-creative.

    This

    suggests

    that

    its

    infinitude is

    not

    to

    be

    understood

    as

    a

    difference

    in

    degree

    from the

    objective

    realities

    of

    our

    other

    ideas,

    but

    rather

    as

    a

    difference

    in kind. It

    is

    the

    apprehension

    of

    this

    self-creative

    power

    which

    provides

    the

    meditator

    with the

    meaning

    of

    necessary

    existence.

    Second,

    the

    collapse

    of

    the

    distinction

    between the

    power

    within

    the

    idea

    and

    the

    efficient

    cause

    of that

    power

    means

    that it will

    be

    impossible

    to

    distinguish the objective reality of the idea from the formal reality which

    is its

    cause.

    In

    other

    words,

    the

    meditator

    will not

    be able

    to

    distinguish

    the idea from the

    thing.

    This

    result

    may

    well

    capture

    the

    true

    sense

    in

    which

    this

    idea

    most

    fully

    escapes

    a

    suspicion

    of material

    falsity?it

    eliminates the

    possibility

    of

    error

    in

    our

    judgments

    since

    there

    is

    nothing

    to

    which

    our

    causal

    principles

    need

    lead

    us.

    And

    it

    may

    also

    reflect

    the full

    sense

    in

    which

    we

    come

    to

    know that

    God

    must

    be the

    cause

    of

    this

    idea.

    These

    epistemological

    results

    demand

    that further

    work

    be

    done

    to

    fully

    answer

    Yolton's

    question. Up

    to

    now,

    the

    meditator

    has taken the

    power

    exhibited inhis ideas to represent his own mind's generative power. Rec

    ognizing

    that

    the

    power

    exhibited

    in

    this

    idea is

    not

    his

    own

    forces

    a

    consideration

    of the

    relationship

    between his

    own

    power

    and God's

    power?the

    second

    stage

    of the

    Meditation

    III

    proof

    passes

    to

    that

    very

    issue.

    The

    full resolution

    of this

    issue

    will

    have

    a

    range

    of

    implications

    concerning

    the

    proper

    understanding

    of the

    mind's

    operations,

    whether the

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:02:37 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Descartes on the Power of Ideas

    12/12

    DESCARTES

    ON

    THE POWER OF IDEAS

    297

    mind is

    in

    fact

    a

    substance,

    and

    more.

    Those

    concerns

    are

    beyond

    the

    scope

    of our

    present

    discussion. It is

    enough

    fornow ifour

    analysis

    has

    provided

    some

    helpful

    results

    regarding

    Descartes'

    theory

    of ideas

    and has

    moti

    vated further

    investigation

    in the directions

    we

    have

    pointed

    out.

    St. John's

    University

    Received

    September

    29,

    1995

    NOTES

    1.

    Stephen

    I.

    Wagner,

    Descartes'Wax:

    Discovering

    the Nature of

    Mind,

    History

    of

    Philosophy

    Quarterly,

    vol.

    12

    (1995), pp.

    165-83.

    2.

    Our

    view,

    in

    line

    with Descartes'

    statement

    in

    the

    Synopsis,

    denies

    that

    Descartes held

    a

    non-representational

    view

    of the

    mind,

    as

    some

    commentators

    have

    suggested,

    e.g.

    Michel

    Henry,

    The

    Soul

    According

    to Descartes

    in

    Stephen

    Voss,

    ed.,

    Essays

    on

    the

    Philosophy

    and Science

    of

    Rene

    Descartes

    (New

    York:

    Oxford

    University

    Press, 1993),

    pp.

    40-51.

    3.

    For

    example,

    Calvin

    Normore,

    Meaning

    and

    Objective Being:

    Descartes

    and

    His

    Sources,

    in

    Am?lie

    Rorty,

    ed.,

    Essays

    on

    Descartes' Meditations

    (Berkeley:

    University

    of California

    Press,

    1986), p.

    238.

    4. See also Third

    Replies,

    AT

    VII,

    181;

    CSM

    II,

    127.

    5. E. J. Ashworth, Descartes' Theory of Objective Reality, The New Scholasti

    cism,

    vol.

    49

    (1975), p.

    338.

    6.

    Annette

    Baier,

    The

    Idea of

    the True

    God

    in

    Descartes,

    in

    Am?lie

    Rorty,

    ed.,

    op.

    cit.,

    p.

    364.

    7.

    The closest Descartes

    comes

    to

    attributing

    such

    power

    to

    ideas

    is

    his

    statement

    that one idea

    may

    perhaps

    originate

    from

    another

    (AT

    VII,

    42;

    CSM

    II,

    29).

    But

    he

    immediately

    goes

    on

    to

    argue

    that

    we

    cannot

    explain

    this

    origination

    without

    appealing

    to

    some

    formal

    reality

    as

    the

    primary

    cause.

    This conclusion

    only

    follows

    if

    he is

    assuming

    that

    ideas do

    not

    themselves

    have

    generative

    power.

    8.

    Nicholas

    Jolley,

    The

    Light

    of

    the

    Soul

    (New

    York: Oxford

    University

    Press,

    1990),

    pp.

    13-14.

    9.

    Vere

    Chappell,

    The

    Theory

    of

    Ideas,

    in

    Am?lie

    Rorty, ed., op. cit., p.

    187.

    10.

    Calvin

    Normore,

    op.

    cit.,

    p.

    230.

    Normore here

    credits

    Margaret

    Wilson

    with

    establishing

    this

    point.

    11.

    John

    Yolton,

    Perceptual

    Acquaintance

    From Descartes

    to

    Reid

    (Minneapolis:

    University

    of Minnesota

    Press, 1984),

    note

    14,

    p.

    41.

    12.

    Versions of this

    paper

    were

    presented

    at

    the fall

    1995

    meetings

    of the

    Midwest

    Seminar

    in

    the

    History

    of

    Early

    Modern

    Philosophy

    and

    the Minnesota

    Philosophi

    cal

    Society. My

    thanks

    go

    to

    the

    organizers

    and

    discussants

    of

    those

    meetings

    (especially

    Phil

    Cummins,

    Michelle

    Eliot

    and

    Doug

    Lewis)

    for

    their

    help

    with

    my

    work.