constitutionalism, legitimacy and modernity in the ... · pdf file2 constitutionalism,...
Post on 09-Dec-2018
214 views
Embed Size (px)
TRANSCRIPT
Constitutionalism, legitimacy and modernity
in the political philosophy of
Eric Voegelin, Leo Strauss and Michael Oakeshott
[Draft please do not cite]
Nol OSullivan
Hull University
UK
November 2010
2
Constitutionalism, legitimacy and modernity in the political philosophy of
Eric Voegelin, Leo Strauss and Michael Oakeshott,
Abstract: The principal concern of European defenders of liberal democracy after the
Second World War was to restate the case for constitutional government in terms that
would provide a conclusive critique of totalitarian ideology in all its forms. What
united Michael Oakeshott, Leo Strauss and Eric Voegelin was their shared
commitment to this task. Beneath this unity of purpose, however, lay profound
disagreement about the precise meaning of constitutionalism and the nature of its
relation, more generally, to Western modernity.
The aim of the present paper is to suggest that Oakeshott alone develops a
coherent conception of modern constitutionalism, mainly because he alone focuses
systematically on the problem to which constitutionalism in its ethical and non-
instrumental form is a response. This is the problem of legitimacy which first emerged
at the beginning of the modern period in the form of the question: under what
conditions can obligation to law exist in a non-voluntary association (i.e. the state)
whose members desire a self-chosen life?
In the pre-modern era, the problem of legitimacy in this distinctively modern
form could not arise due to the assumption that the power of rulers over subjects is
rationally or divinely ordained by the order of the universe itself. In the modern
period, however, this kind of cosmically grounded concept of legitimacy is no longer
available. In its absence, the only viable modern response consists in constructing a
public realm in which both rulers and ruled participate, thereby making politics more
than mere power or domination. Accordingly, the main condition for political
legitimacy in modern Western liberal democracies is, in Oakeshotts words, that a
government must be constituted in such a way that it can be considered as belonging
to the governed and not as an alien power.1 In practice, representative government
has been the means of achieving this outcome.
When Oakeshotts identification of the primary condition for political
legitimacy is borne in mind, the principal failing of Strauss and Voegelin as defenders
1 Oakeshott, M. (200), The Concept of Government in Modern Europe, in Collingwood and British Idealism Studies, 12, 17-35. First published as La Idea de Gobierno en la Europa Moderna (Madrid: Ateneo, 1955). This was a Spanish translation of a lecture delivered in English at the Ateneo, Madrid.
3
of constitutionalism is immediately apparent: it is their tendency to evade the problem
due to their dominant concern with comprehensive cultural critiques focused on
nihilism, in Strausss case, and on secularized forms of the Gnostic heresy, in
Voegelins. As a result of this concern with cultural critique, both thinkers fail to
disengage the conditions for political legitimacy from the intellectual and moral
conditions for spiritual order.
In Strausss case, the form of constitutionalism he favoured was the ancient
kind resting on wisdom and virtue, rather than the modern procedural kind. The
central problem presented by his political thought, however, is that his critique of
modern constitutionalism from a classical standpoint is open to the charge of being a
caricature, a charge which may be made quite regardless of the truth or falsity of his
belief that classical thought has a secret or esoteric character designed to conceal a
message which only the privileged scholar may penetrate.
In Voegelins case, as in Strausss, a commitment to constitutionalism was at
odds with his desire to protect postwar democracy from subversion by the Gnostic
yearning for salvation which he believed had inspired modern radical ideologies (and
continues to inspire neo-conservatism, for example). The outcome in both instances
was potentially authoritarian sympathies which were more likely to subvert any
modern constitution than to defend it.
What distinguishes Oakeshott from both thinkers is his commitment to an
essentially procedural form of constitutionalism expressed in the juridical ideal of
civil association as alone appropriate to Western modernity. It will be argued that
although Oakeshotts ideal of civil association is difficult to extricate from the
integrating aspects of nationalism, economic prosperity and welfare policy which
have accompanied its historical development in the nation state, it nevertheless,
remains the only conception of constitutionalism that offers a coherent response to the
problem of legitimacy that is, to reconciling authority with freedom.
***********
The principal concern of European defenders of a free society after the Second
World War was to mount a critique of totalitarianism which would ensure that it never
recurred in Western liberal democracies. What united Michael Oakeshott, Leo Strauss
and Eric Voegelin was the belief that this critique must take the form of a defence of
4
constitutional government. The three thinkers disagreed profoundly, however, about
precisely what constitutionalism means, as well as about the crisis of modernity which
they believe threatens it. Eric Voegelins treatment of these issues will be considered
first.
Voegelin
Voegelin believed that the form of constitutionalism adopted by liberal
democracies after 1945 provides no protection against the return of dictatorship
because it offers no remedy for the spiritual malaise which, after inspiring the radical
ideologies of the inter-war era, continues unabated into the post-war decades, after.
This malaise he attributed to a secularized version of the ancient Gnostic heresy, the
essence of which is the experience of the existing order as a prison from which
liberation must be sought by violence if necessary. In its secularized and politicized
form, the Gnostic experience consists of alienation from the established social order
so profound that ideologies offering the prospect of an escape from it by revolution
are welcomed.
It is not relevant in the present context to explore Voegelins interpretation of
the stages by which he believes Gnosticism was gradually transformed from a
religious heresy (as the Church labelled it) during the early centuries AD into a
secularized interpretation of history from the time of Joachim of Fiore in the twelfth
century. Thereafter, the process of immanentizing the Christian eschaton, as
Voegelin termed it, led to a political vision of earthly salvation through revolutionary
violence which eventually triumphed in the totalitarian ideologies of the twentieth
century. The seven league boots worn by Voegelin in the course of his account of the
two millennia during which he argues that the transformation occurred, it need hardly
be said, have been criticized on the ground that his giant strides testify more to his
speculative ability than to his regard for historical accuracy. What is more to the point
is that, ironically, his desire to protect post-war democracy from subversion by
Gnostic-inspired authoritarian political movements led him to sympathize with a
potentially authoritarian solution more likely to subvert modern liberal democratic
constitutions than to protect them.
The tension between constitutionalism and authoritarianism in Voegelins
political thought is evident above all in a crucial distinction he made in The New
5
Science of Politics (1952) between two different kinds of representation in the course
of specifying the kind of reform required in order to place liberal democracy on a
secure foundation. One kind is what he termed elemental representation, and the
other, existential representation. By elemental representation Voegelin referred to
the formal system of popular elections on which modern western liberal democracies
rely. Its weakness is that it leaves a society at the mercy of any Gnostic tendencies to
which the masses are prone. By existential representation, he referred to a system in
which the ruler is representative in the deeper sense that the values he stands for
reflect the societys whole way of life.2 Voegelins contention was that only a
democracy based on the latter, existential kind of representation is secure against
extremist movements like Nazism because it permits power to be placed in the hands
of an lite which is free from Gnostic tendencies.
As Hans Kelsen, one of Voegelins former doctoral supervisors, was not slow
to point out, the concept of existential representation could easily sanction exactly the
kind of totalitarian system Voegelin opposed, since it permitted the Soviet
government, for example, to claim to be the existential rep