2016 conference proceedings

32
PROCEEDINGS OF THE 12’TH SWECOG CONFERENCE GÖTEBORG, OCTOBER 6-7, 2016 BY SWEDISH COGNITIVE SCIENCE SOCIETY EDITORS Alexander Almér Robert Lowe Erik Billing

Upload: hoanganh

Post on 03-Jan-2017

245 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: 2016 Conference Proceedings

PROCEEDINGS OF THE 12’THSWECOG CONFERENCE

GÖTEBORG, OCTOBER 6-7, 2016

BY SWEDISH COGNITIVE SCIENCE SOCIETY

EDITORSAlexander AlmérRobert LoweErik Billing

Page 2: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Copyright c© 2016 The Authors

Skovde University Studies in Informatics 2016:2ISBN 978-91-983667-0-9ISSN 1653-2325

PUBLISHED BY THE UNIVERSITY OF SKOVDE

Page 3: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Preface

Welcome to SweCog 2016!

This booklet contains the abstracts of all oral and poster presentations at the 2016SweCog conference. Following the SweCog tradition, with the aim to support net-working among researchers in Sweden, contributions cover a wide spectrum of cogni-tive science research.

Here you will find work on e.g. concept formation, human decision making, ethics,emotions, and programming. One of the most frequent objects of study is interaction,not only between humans, but also between humans and technology. Technology isvery present also in a different way, providing the fundament for research on artificialintelligence. Several contributions related to artificial life test the boundaries for whatwe see as cognition. As artificial intelligence and related techniques become increas-ingly common in artifacts interacting with people, we see these themes growing closerto each other.

We would like to thank the many people that have contributed to this conference andin particular all authors and reviewers.

The reviewers were: Alexander Almer, Erik Billing, Pierre Gander, Mikael Jensen,Rob Lowe, and Claes Strannegard.

1

Page 4: 2016 Conference Proceedings

2

Page 5: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Conference Program

Conference chairs: Alexander Almér and Rob Lowe

Thursday 6th of October

10:00 — 10:45

Registration at Lindholmen Science Park, (outside ) conference hall Pascal Friday October seven is spent in Tesla, a lecture hall alongside Pascal Coffee will be served

10:45 — 11:00 Conference opening

11:00 — 12:00 Invited speaker: Judith Simon, IT University Copenhagen and University of Vienna Big Data: Extended, Android or Collective Cognition

12:00 — 12:30 Mattias Arvola

12:30 — 13:30 Lunch

13:30 — 14:00 Robert Johansson

14:00 — 14:30 Claes Strannegård

14:30 — 15:00 Robert Lowe

15.00 — 15:30 Coffee break

15:30 — 16:00 Mattias Forsblad (Kristiansson)

16.00 — 17:00

Poster session, starting with 5 minutes doctoral student oral (poster) presentations: Kajsa Nalin (p.); Simon Klein (p); Azadeh Hassanejad Nazir (p. ); Veronica Petrovych (p.); Leon Sütfeld (p.); Nils Dahlbäck (p.); Richard Johansson (p.) Luís Trabasso (p.)

17.00 — 18.00 Panel debate

19.00 (around) Dinner at Vapiano, Östra Hamngatan 35. We are departing around 18.30 taking a free ferry from Lindholmspiren, and then walk a few minutes to the restaurant.

3

Page 6: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Friday 7th of October

09:00 — 10:00 Invited speaker: Christian Balkenius, Lund University (conference hall Tesla ) Spatial indexing, coding and memory

10:00 — 10.30 Coffee break

10:30 — 11:00 Sam Thellman

11:00 — 11:30 Mikael Jensen

11:30 — 12:00 Gordana Dodig-Crnkovic

12.00 — 13:00 Lunch

13:00 — 13:30 Ulf Persson

13.30 — 14.00 Joel Parthemore

Final words

14.05 — 14.45 SweCog annual meeting

4

Page 7: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Transmodal Interaction and User Experience

Mattias Arvola1, Mathias Nordvall1, 2 &Mathias Broth3

1Department of Computer and Information Science, Linköping University

2SICS East Swedish ICT

3Department of Culture and Communication, Linköping University

[email protected]

We are in a series of studies, ranging from news production to computer gaming, looking into the intersection of transmodal interaction and user experience. The purpose of this abstract is to outline the theoretical framework for that intersection. The first area we are studying is Transmodal Interaction, which is a concept that refer to a specific aspect of multimodal interaction. Human action is multimodal (Streeck, Goodwin, & LeBaron, 2011), and different sensory modes play an important role in action. However, little attention has been given to the intricate ways in which sensory modalities (seeing – drawing, hearing – saying, moving – touching, etc.) integrate, affect, and transform each other during the course of an activity. There are transformations of meaning in every new materialisation of an idea or a thought, partly depending on the communication potential of the sensory modality. This render what we refer to as a transmodal process where ideas and thoughts materialise action by action in an emergent sequence across relatively long and discontinuous timespans (Murphy, 2012). Over a sequence of actions, the meanings expressed in one modality, dynamically blend and shape what is expressed in other modalities. This produces, according to (Murphy, 2012) “a series of semiotic modulations in which certain core qualities persist, but others are noticeably transformed in the transition from one mode to another. (p. 1969)” We can, in intersemiotic translation (Jakobson, 1959) between modalities, address what is lost, how we introduce distortions, or even introduce perceptions of things that do not exist. A question is then how continuity of meaning and experience is preserved in modality changes. The second area we are studying is User Experience. The term refers to a person's perceptions and responses resulting from the use and/or anticipated use of a product, system or service (ISO, 2010). We employ a three level model of user experience based on Leontiev’s account of consciousness (Kaptelinin & Nardi, 2012; Leont´ev, 1978), which also relate closely to Norman’s model of emotional design (Norman, 2005). The first level is the sensory fabric of consciousness, Norman refers to this as the visceral level. It is the largely subconscious level of how things feel. The second level is the personal meaning of things, related to what and how we do things action by action. Norman (ibid.) refers to this level as the behavioural level. The third level has to do with meaning, and what Norman refers to as a reflective level. It is the level of cultural meaning and what things mean for us in our socially and historically rooted activities. The intersection of these two areas constitutes our current focus of research. We are, in domains as different as news production and computer gaming, investigating persons’ perceptions and actions resulting from interaction with each other and with materialisations across different sensory modalities that give rise to intersemiotic translation effects.

References

ISO. (2010). ISO 9241-210: 2010 Ergonomics of human-system interaction -- Part 210: Human-centred design. Geneva: International Standardization Organization.

Jakobson, R. (1959). On linguistic aspects of translation. In R. A. Brower (Ed.), On translation (pp. 232-239). Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

Kaptelinin, V., & Nardi, B. (2012). Activity theory in HCI: Fundamentals and Reflections. Synthesis Lectures on Human-Centered Informatics, 5(1), 1-105.

Leont´ev, A. N. (1978). Activity, Consciousness, and Personality. Englewood Cliffs, NJ.: Prentice-Hall. Murphy, K. M. (2012). Transmodality and temporality in design interactions. Journal of Pragmatics, 44(14),

1966-1981. doi:10.1016/j.pragma.2012.08.013 Norman, D. A. (2005). Emotional design: Why we love (or hate) everyday things. New York, NY.: Basic Books. Streeck, J. r., Goodwin, C., & LeBaron, C. (2011). Embodied interaction: language and body in the material

world. Cambridge, Mass.: Cambridge University Press.

5

Page 8: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Similarities and differences between professional and everyday environments as

distributed cognitive systems

Nils Dahlbäck1, Mattias Forsblad (Kristiansson)1

1Department of Computer and Information Science, Linköping University

{nils.dahlback; mattias.forsblad}@liu.se

There are many views on what distributed cognition is and is not. These can be grouped into two major

categories. One views distributed cognition as something specific to professional environments and the teams

working there (e.g.Rogers and Ellis, 1994). The other view claims that distributed cognition is a perspective on

all cognition (e.g Hutchins, 2013). By studying an environment maximally separated from the professional

environments usually studied, i.e. the home of persons living alone, we found it possible to meaningfully analyze

also these with methods and concepts from distributed cognition, and thereby finding support for the latter

interpretation (Forsblad, 2016, Dahlbäck and Kristiansson, 2016). In this paper we focus on describing the

similarities and differences between those two environments, and suggest reasons for these.

The perhaps fundamental difference between these two distributed cognitive systems is that while professional

environments are specifically designed for one particular task, homes are multi-purpose systems. Another

important difference is that professional environments are about controlling complex activities from a distance,

whereas almost, but not all, of the activities in the home take place there and are less complex. A consequence of

the latter is that tools that carry representational content are more frequent in the professional than in the

everyday environments. There are of course also representational tools in the home environments, but it is

interesting to note that these are primarily connected to activities outside the home.

A consequence of the fact that the environment is multi-purpose is that many functional spaces and cues are of

necessity hidden because of space limitations. Multifunctional spaces and space limitations also have an impact

on the persons’ maintenance practices, where we in many cases find that the persons engage as an on-going

routine in on-the-go maintenance practices when they encounter a displaced object, whereas in many

professional environments these primarily occur after finished tasks.

But despite these differences, we also see large similarities between the professional and home environments

when viewed as distributed systems. The persons living in the homes have routines for not only maintenance but

also for cognitive tasks like remembering intentions of future activities,, where the places in the home, tools and

the routines combine to serve a cognitive function. This is very similar to what is seen in how experts act in

professional environments, something which lends support to Kirsh’s (2009) claim that most people become

experts or near-experts in their everyday environments. We also find that the routines and tools used often are

based on what has been learned and appropriated from other persons, often from an older generation, so here we

find forms of cultural knowledge accumulation across generations, just like in e.g. Hutchins (1995) analysis of

maritime navigation. So while on the surface there are important differences between professional and everyday

distributed cognitive systems, when looking closer we find many similarities. All in all this supports the view

that the methods and concepts of distributed cognition are a useful approach for studying many kinds of

cognition.

References

Dahlbäck, Nils & Kristiansson, Mattias (2016), A perspective on all cognition? A study of everyday

environments from the perspective of distributed cognition. In Proceedings of the Annual Conference of the

Cognitive Society (CogSci 2016).

Forsblad (Kristiansson), Mattias (2016) Distributed cognition in home environments: the prospective memory

and cognitive practices of older adults. Linköping Studies in Arts and Science Dissertation No. 695

Hutchins, Edwin (1995) Cognition in the Wild. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Hutchins, E. (2013). The cultural ecosystem of human cognition. Philosophical Psychology, (September), 1–16. 6

Page 9: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Kirsh, David (2009) Problem solving and situated cognition. In: Robbins, P., & Aydede, M. (Eds.). The

Cambridge Handbook of Situated Cognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Rogers, Y., & Ellis, J. (1994). Distributed cognition: An alternative framework for analysing and explaining

collaborative working. Journal of Information Technology, 9(2), 119–128.

7

Page 10: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Morphological computing as reality construction for a cognizing agent

Gordana Dodig-Crnkovic

Department of Applied IT

Chalmers University of Technology and Gothenburg University

[email protected]

In this talk I will give a short account of my view of the process of reality construction in cognitive agent through morphological computation, within the framework of info-computational constructivism as generative modeling scheme (Dodig-Crnkovic 2014a, 2014b, 2016). Cognition in this framework is capacity possessed in different forms and degrees of complexity by every living organism. It is entirety of processes going on in an organism that keeps it alive, and present as a distinct agent in the world. Even a single cell while alive constantly cognizes, that is registers inputs from the world and its own body, ensures its own continuous existence through metabolism and food hunting while avoiding dangers that could cause its disintegration or damage, at the same time adapting its own morphology to the environmental constraints. The entirety of physico-chemical processes depends on the morphology of the organism, where morphology is meant as the form and structure. The essential property of morphological computing is that it is defined on a structure of nodes (agents) that exchange (communication) of information. Unicellular organisms such as bacteria communicate and build swarms or films with far more advanced capabilities compared to individual organisms, through social (distributed) cognition. In general, groups of smaller organisms (cells) in nature cluster into bigger ones (multicellular assemblies) with differentiated control mechanisms from the cell level to the tissue, organ, organism and groups of organisms, and this layered organization provides information processing benefits.

With the development of specific nervous system, multicellular organisms acquire ability of self-representation, which enables distinction between “me” and the “other” and presents basic functionality that will support locomotion. Plants that do not move freely in space and have control implemented on the level of chemical signals, while animals possess nervous systems with brains and connection to diverse sensory organs which developed to provide capability of locomotion. Brains in animals also consist of many cells mutually communicating. Interesting and unexpected is the fact that single neuron is a relatively simple information processor, while the whole brain possesses advanced cognizing capacities. There are several questions of interest to study in light of evolution of cognition from the simplest to the most complex cognitive systems. Those are, among others: What are the most important differences between organisms with control mechanisms based solely on physico-chemical regulation and those which possess hierarchy of mechanisms from physico-chemical to symbolic information processing that always takes place in nervous system and brain? How dos the computation (information processing) differ in brain and in other nervous system? What establishes “the reality” or the “representation” of the world within an agent in its bodily structures and processes? How does the process on the basic level go on that constitutes every cognitive computation: physico-chemical processes in the agents’ body? How does morphology influence what can be computed within a physical system (organism) and how development is shaped by the computational (information processing) properties?

References

Dodig-Crnkovic, G. (2014a) Modeling Life as Cognitive Info-Computation, In: Computability in Europe 2014, Arnold Beckmann, Erzsébet Csuhaj-Varjú and Klaus Meer (Eds.) Proceedings of the 10th Computability in Europe 2014, Language, Life, Limits, Budapest, Hungary, June 23 - 27, 2014, LNCS, Springer

Dodig-Crnkovic, G. (2014b) Info-computational Constructivism and Cognition, Constructivist Foundations (2014), 9(2) pp. 23-231 (target article)

Dodig-Crnkovic, G. (2016) Information, Computation, Cognition. Agency-Based Hierarchies of Levels. FUNDAMENTAL ISSUES OF ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE, Müller V. C. (ed.), Synthese Library 377, pp 139-159. Springer International Publishing Switzerland. 8

Page 11: 2016 Conference Proceedings

The practices of finding lost objects: a video based case analysis

Mattias Forsblad (Kristiansson)

Department of Computer and Information Science

Division for Human-Centered Systems, Linköping University

[email protected]

Finding lost objects in real everyday life seems to be seldom studied situation. Smith and Cohen, (2008) give an

overview of the field, where I note that, despite a few studies on finding your car in the parking lot, the only

exception is Tenney (1984) who used a questionnaire to compare older with younger adults. She, for instance,

found no difference between younger and older adults in how often they experienced such situation, instead it

was instead attributed to absentmindedness. The only age difference was that older adults reported a higher

frequency of a defective search or failure of detecting the object in plain sight. However, since the study was

based on self-reports the empirical descriptions of mechanisms are not in detail. In my presentation I give an in-

detail video analysis of a two-minute search situation where one person needs to find her bus and exercise cards

just before leaving home. This analysis gives insights into some mechanisms of a defective and effective search

in everyday life.

A number of objects and spaces are involved in the search: a small handbag, pockets of a medium sized shoulder

bag for exercise, pockets on five (out of seven) jackets located. She searches the shoulder bag twice and in fact

eventually finds the card in the shoulder bag in the only pocket she did not search the first time. The search of

these spaces are interesting for several reasons. Two of these reasons are:

First it highlights a cognitive process involving physical resources that are out of plain sight. However,

perceptual processes can still play a role. The analysis shows that a likely reason that the target pocket was an

unlikely location was that the pocket looked like one that does not primarily contain flat objects, in fact, it also

contained a pair of glasses that made the pocket look bulky. Second the search is driven by exhaustive search

actions and deliberate memory and decisions overriding the more automatic actions. This is particularly clear in

how she quickly searches pockets in the jackets and deliberately skips two of them.

Altogether, the mixture of episodic remembering, perceptual interpretive decisions, and knowledge (semantic

memories) about the typical orderings of her environment is what makes the search far more sophisticated than a

space-exhaustive one would be. However, this is also what seems to be the reason why the search takes longer

than might have been necessary. The analysis highlights that the person is aware that searches can be defective

and therefore distrusts the thoroughness of her previous actions.

Finally, the analysis of homes (Forsblad, 2016, forthcoming) also suggest that misplacement is not necessarily

about absentmindedness. It is also a consequence of that in homes objects can have multiple locations as a

consequence of past activities. The issue is therefore first more about what experimental studies call updating

errors, and second, not having a routine of re-arranging objects when coming home. What can seem a small

search tree outside homes can easily become a larger one when coming home.

References

Forsblad, M. (2016). Distributed cognition in home environments: The prospective memory and cognitive

practices of older adults. Doctoral thesis: Linköping University.

Smith, A. D., & Cohen, G. (2008). Memory for places: Routes, maps, and objects locations. In G. Cohen & M.

A. Conway (Eds.), Memory in the real world (Third Edit, pp. 173–206). Psychology Press.

Tenney, Y. J. (1984). Ageing and the misplacing of objects. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 2(1),

43–50.

9

Page 12: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Functional mapping as means for establishing a human factors research

environment for future air systems

Luís Gonzaga Trabasso1, Jens Alfredson2

1Aeronautics Institute of Technology, Dept. of Mechanical Engineering &LiU, Department of Computer

and Information Science

2SAAB: Aeronautics Human Machine Interaction & LiU, Department of Computer and Information

Science

Presenter’s e-mail address:[email protected]

A typical environment for human factors research has equipment and methods for performing a set of

experiments such as mental workload assessment, situational awareness evaluation, human resilience

measurement and so forth. The common aspect between equipment and methods is that they accomplish a

function. The TLX method (Hart, 2006) is part of such an environment because it evaluates the mental

workload; an EEG helmet (Borghini, 2014) is part of the same research environment because it measures

the electrical activity originated by the brain. If the functional structure of a method or equipment is yet to

be known, a method for function deployment might be used to this purpose such as FAST (Bartolomei,

2001).Although cognitive processes in many regards are very different from functions in technical systems,

it is possible to describe them in terms of functions for the sake using it for design considerations. For

instance, the information-processing paradigm has inspired descriptions that in some regards could be

described in functional terms. The multiple resource theory (Wickens, 2008) that outlines different mental

resources related to various modalities and stages of processing is another example of that. Then a

functional mapping engine identifies the equipment and method that address the cognitive functions

required for a given experiment. A very simple example of functional mapping is as follows: the cognitive

module <vision> has a function X {to track objects}. The equipment *eye tracker* and the method # EPOG

– Eye Point of Gaze# have the functions Y [To look at through computer vision] and Z [to track objects].

The mapping among functions X, Y and Z indicate the equipment and method are suitable for addressing

the cognitive characteristic under investigation. On the one hand, if an equipment or method do exist, then

the functional mapping assist the research environment designer to identify them and help choosing if

several options are available. On the other hand, if an equipment or method do not exist, then the functional

mapping assist the research environment designer to design and build them. Moving forward from the very

simple example to a more practical and realistic situation, the functional mapping can tackle the issues of

choosing the necessary functions – from both sides, cognitive and equipment and methods – to meet fidelity

requirements of an experiment. This is suggested to be resolved by the cost-benefit tradeoff approach

detailed as follows. Based on the functional mapping, selective fidelity can be obtained for modeling and

simulation considerations. Thereby advantages and disadvantages of the human factors research

environment for future air systems could be balanced by the functional mapping, potentially optimizing the

use of simulations. System border definition ought to be considered; the border definition practice borrowed

from aircraft product/system configuration can be used to this end. Selective fidelity has been applied to

transfer of training in military aviation (Borgvall, et al. 2007) and simulator based design has been shown

to be useful for development of air systems (Alm, 2007). The proposed functional mapping approach could

have the potential of adding to this tradition.

References

Alm, T. (2007). Simulator-based design: Methodology and vehicle display applications. Doctoral

dissertation (No. 1078). Linköping, Sweden: Linköping University.

Bartolomei, J. E. & Miller, T. (2001). Functional Analysis Systems Technique (F.A.S.T.) as a Group

Knowledge Elicitation Method for Model Building. Proceedings of 19th International Conference of

the System Dynamics Society, Atlanta, GE, USA. 10

Page 13: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Borghini, G., et al. (2014). Measuring neurophysiological signals in aircraft pilots and car drivers for the

assessment of mental workload, fatigue and drowsiness. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 44:58-75.

Borgvall, J., Castor, M., Nählinder, S., Oskarsson, P. A., & Svensson, E. (2007). Transfer of training in

military aviation. Command and control systems, Swedish defence research agency (FOI).

Hart, S.G. (2006). NASA-Task Load Index (NASA-TLX); 20 years later. Proceedings of the Human

Factors and Ergonomics Society, San Francisco, CA, USA.

Wickens, C. D. (2008). Multiple Resources and Mental Workload. Human Factors, 50(3), 449-455.

11

Page 14: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Three neural structures, Amygdala, orbitofrontal cortex (OFC) and Lateral prefrontal cortex (LPFC) are major structures underlying DM process. The first two structures underpin the emotional DM through encoding the internal and external stimuli (Ghashghaei & Barbas, 2000) while LPFC takes over the cognitive valuation of potential course of actions through coding external stimuli (Dixon & Christoff, 2014). The oscillatory activities of these neural structures represent the values of the options based on the amplitude, frequency and the size of the cell assemblies. The integration of the emotional and cognitive values results in the process of final values of the options. The competition among values brings the final decision.

Learning through observing occurred with regard to the extent of observational information; observation of the action or action-outcome. In the former case, the learnings based on the action observation are followed with mirroring the behavior with regard to the expected value of the observed action. Observing the action-outcome causes the prediction error generation and update of the neural dynamic properties. Reinforcement learning (either vicarious or based on the personal experience) modifies synaptic strength among neural populations and the size of the cell assembly associated to the subjective values of the actions. Trust has a major role in the properties of the prediction error (magnitude and sign) and feedback learning. The probability of being influenced by the society is computed with Bayesian probability.

Contribution of trust to the decision making process based on the observational learning

Azadeh Hassannejad Nazir1, Hans Liljenström1,2

1Division of Biometry and system Analysis, ET, SLU, Uppsala, SE-75007, Sweden

2Agora for Biosystems, SE-19322, Sweden

[email protected]

The dynamics of a society is the corollary of the individuals’ interactions. Attitude as the cornerstone of the individual’s motivation for decision making (DM) is considered the emerged repercussions of the social dynamics. Decision making as an adaptive process is performed with regard to the subjective perspectives (Peters & Büchel, 2010) indicating the influence of the society over the individuals. Among parameters that might affect the valuation process, trust is pivotal to the positive subjective valuation and the spread of attitudes that might end in changing the behavior. DM process at the social level is executed based on different types of learning in the social contexts (Fiske, 1993). This project concerns the computational modeling of social DM hinged upon observational learning pursuing the role of trust in behavior change. This process is regarded as the framework for mimicking the social behavior with the focus on the expected value of the observed action/outcome (Burke, et al. 2010).

Regarding Kahneman’s postulation, dual thinking, decision making is interplay between emotion (system 1) and cognition (system 2). A decision making model is presented in (Hassannejad Nazir & Liljenström, 2015) at the mesoscopic neurodynamics based on the three-layered neural network (Liljenström, 1991).

Internal and external contexts are major determinants of decisions/behaviors. Trust to the social agents has pivotal role in conforming to their behavior. According to the results, the trust level modulates the motivation of selecting an option and subsequently affects the probability of following the social norms and behaviors. Thus, trust and the level of satisfaction in being modeled on the other agents determine the level of conformity.

12

Page 15: 2016 Conference Proceedings

References

Burke, C.J. Tobler, P.N. Baddeley, M. Schultz, W. (2010 ). Neural mechanisms of observational learning. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A. 107(32):14431-6. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1003111107

Dixon, M.L. & Christoff, K.E. (2014). The lateral prefrontal cortex and complex value-based learning and decision making. Neurosci Biobehav Rev. 45C:9-18.

Fiske, S.T. (1993). Social cognition and social perception. Annu. Rev. Psychology 44:155-194.

Ghashghaei, H.T. & Barbas, H. (2000). Pathways for emotion: interactions of prefrontal and anterior temporal pathways in the amygdala of the rhesus monkey. Neuroscience. 115(4):1261-79.

Hassannejad Nazir, A. & Liljenström, H. (2015). A cortical network model of cognitive and emotional influences in human decision making. BioSystems, 136:128–14.

Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking Fast and Slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

Liljenström H. (1991). Modeling the dynamics of olfactory cortex using simplified network units and realistic architecture. Int. J. Neural Systems, 2, 1-15.

Peters, J. & Büchel, C. (2010 ). Neural representations of subjective reward value. Behav Brain Res. 1;213(2):135-41. doi: 10.1016/j.bbr.2010.04.031

13

Page 16: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Speaker-audience interactive synchrony: a case of embodied speech perception?

Mikael Jensen1, Nataliya Berbyuk Lindström1, & Linnéa Emanuelsson1

1University of Gothenburg, Applied IT, Division of Cognition and Communication

[email protected]

Interactive synchrony as a communicative phenomenon was probably first reported by Condon and Ogston (1966). Egolf and Chester (2013) differentiate between self-other synchrony alpha and self-other synchrony beta. The beta type, that we have tested, is a case of synchrony between the speakers’ body movements and the listeners’ body movements. It has been suggested that interactive synchrony is an effect of rapport (Egolf, 2012) or immediacy (Andersen, 1999). We wanted to find out if interactive synchrony is related to speech comprehension. We designed a test condition building on two factors: (1) a speaker-audience setting at which (2) none of the participants were allowed to speak in their first language. All spoke English. In this way we created some level of stress in the speakers and a reduced possibility to fully comprehend the speech. In other words, the audience had to be alert and work hard to pick up and understand all that was being said. Our hypothesis is that low speech comprehension among the listeners will increase the interactive synchrony. Six speakers and 18 listeners (who remained the same during all performances) were invited. The speech was about five minutes long and focused on the topic of abortion. To measure the body movements we used a motion capture system and markers placed on both speakers’ and listeners’ bodies. The system is very accurate and calculates movement velocity in millimeters per second. We also used a simple questionnaire. After each speech the participants in the audience were asked to assess the clarity of the speaker’s voice. Our assumption is that lack of articulation (and maybe pronunciation) due to second language use will cause audience comprehension to suffer. The voice clarity was graded on a Likert scale from one (very clear) to seven (very unclear). The test condition generated 108 unique dyads between speaker and listener. For each dyad we measured the interactive synchrony by calculating the correlation of velocity in the speaker’s head movements and the listener’s head movements. The correlation coefficient was recalculated into a Speaker-Audience Interactive Synchrony (SPAIS) value. The SPAIS value was in turn tested for correlation and regression analysis with the voice clarity assessment value. The correlation is high (r=0.65, p<0.001) suggesting that interactive synchrony goes together with an unclear voice. The regression analysis indicates that reversed voice clarity overlaps with interactive synchrony by about 43%. This means that the level of voice clarity can explain 43% of the variation of the interactive synchrony. We suggest that if the listener does not hear well enough, the whole body starts to move in synchrony with the speaker’s body movements to enhance speech perception and comprehension. Callan et al. (2003) and Ross et al. (2007) have found that during noisy conditions listeners start to mirror jaw, lip and tongue movements to simulate what is being said. We assume that interactive synchrony might be a similar mechanism to support speech perception. We conclude that our hypothesis is supported.

References

Andersen, P. A. (1999). Nonverbal communication. Forms and functions. London: Mayfield Publishing Company. Callan, D. E. et al. (2003). Neural processes underlying perceptual enhancement by visual speech gestures. NeuroReport, 14

(17), 2213–2218. Condon, W. S., & Ogston, W. D. (1966). Sound film analysis of normal and pathological behavior patterns. Journal of

Nervous and Mental Disease, 143, 338–347. Egolf, D. B. (2012). Human communication and the brain. New York: Lexington Books. Egolf, D. B., & Chester, S. (2013). The nonverbal factor. Exploring the other side of communication. Bloomington, IN:

iUniverse. Ross, L. A. et al. (2007). Do you see what I am saying? Exploring visual enhancement of speech comprehension in noisy

environments. Cerebral Cortex, 17, 1147–1153.

14

Page 17: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Lärande och social kognition: ett utvecklingsperspektiv

Mikael Jensen1

1Department of applied IT, University of Gothenburg

Division of Cognition and Communication

[email protected]

Bakgrund

Pramling genomförde under tidigt 1980-tal en intervjustudie där barn i åldrarna tre till åtta år deltog. Studien innebar att intervjuaren ställde förhållandevis öppna frågor för att ta reda på vad barnen i de olika åldrarna hade för uppfattningar om vad lärande är. Svaren skilde sig åt från en åldersgrupp till en annan. Åttaåringarna gav de mest komplexa svaren (Pramling, 1983). Pramlings studie tog inte hänsyn till lärandesituationens eller lärandeobjektets komplexitet. Gardner (1998; även Wellman, 2004) beskriver hur barn i någon mening greppar skeenden i världen i fysiska termer först, därefter i biologiska termer och slutligen i psykologiska termer. Detta är en förståelse i komplexitetsgrad som utvecklas stegvis. En tänkbar experimentdesign är att visa barn händelser där lärande kan uppfattas som förändringar i fysiska, biologiska och i psykiska termer. Barn kan förstå att de själva lär sig men förstår de att andra lär sig? De välkända false-belief-testen (Perner, 1991; Gopnik & Meltzoff, 2002) visar att barn runt fyra-fem års ålder kan förstå att andra vet något som de själva inte vet. Det gör däremot inte treåringar. Har detta betydelse för hur barn resonerar kring andras lärande? Studier föreslår att sex- och åttaåringar har en mer komplex förståelse kring andras tankar (Dunbar, 2006). Syfte

Syftet med studien är att undersöka komplexitetsgrader av förskole- och skolbarns (3-8 år) förståelse av andras lärande. Om lärande är social till sin natur är det avgörande om barn kan förstå att andra lär sig likaväl som att de själva lär sig. Det är rimligt att det som andra lär sig kan vara olika svårt för en bedömare att greppa. Metod

51 barn i fyra åldersgrupper fick höra en kort berättelse om ett barn som utför något som kan uppfattas som potentiellt lärande. Berättelsen illustreras med en tecknad serie som ryms på ett A4-ark. Efter berättelsen fick deltagaren frågan om huvudpersonen i berättelsen har lärt sig och i så fall vad

huvudpersonen kan ha lärt sig. Proceduren upprepades med totalt sex korta berättelser. Två av berättelserna skildrar händelser som kan tolkas som fysiska skeenden, två kan tolkas som biologiska och två kan tolkas som psykologiska processer. Deltagarnas responser spelades in med videokamera och deltagarnas svar antecknades direkt efter varje berättelse. En statistisk analys användes. Resultat

Det är en påtaglig skillnad i hur treåringarna och åttaåringarna svarar på frågorna. Åttaåringarna svarade generellt oftare ja på frågan om huvudpersonen hade lärt sig något. Den största skillnaden gick dock att finna i vad barnen svarade att huvudpersonen hade lärt sig. Treåringarna gav mycket sällan relaterade svar. Åttaåringarna gav relaterade svar på en hög komplexitetsnivå. Sexåringarna var nära åttaåringarna i sina svar medan fyraåringarna var nära treåringarna. Tre- och fyraåringarna hade lättast att sätta sig in i innehållet som rörde fysiska skeenden. Sex- och åttaåringarna hade lättast för att sätta sig in i biologiska och psykologiska processer. Sammantaget är det skillnad på barns förståelse av andras lärande baserat på åldersskillnader. Social kognition har en inverkan på lärande. Förklaringar kan ligga i barns förmåga till theory of mind och arbetsminnets kapacitet.

Referenser Dunbar, R. (2006). Historien om människan. Ludvika: Dualis. Gardner, H. (1998). Så tänker barn – och så borde skolan undervisa. Jönköping: Brain books. Gopnik, A. & Meltzoff A. N. (2002). Words, thoughts, and theories. Cambridge, MA: A Bradford Book. Perner, J. (1991). Understanding the representational mind. London: A Bradford book. Pramling, I. (1983). The child’s conception of learning. Doktorsavhandling. Göteborg: Acta Universitatis

Gothoburgensis. Wellman, H. M. (2004). Understanding the psychological world: developing a theory of mind. In U. Goswami (ed.),

Blackwell handbook of childhood cognitive development. Oxford: Blackwell publishing. 15

Page 18: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Combining symbolic and distributional concept representations

Richard Johansson

Department of Computer Science and EngineeringUniversity of Gothenburg & Chalmers University of Technology

[email protected]

Developing practical representations of concepts is crucial in a wide range of computational applications, includingnatural language processing (NLP) applications such as web search, information extraction and question answering.Hand-engineered, knowledge-based approaches to concept representation is carried out by defining a large inventoryof symbols, and then the meaning of each symbol is defined in terms of typed relations to other symbols, using someframework of knowledge representation. From these relations, we can infer implicit facts not explicitly listed: amotorcycle IS_A wheeled vehicle, so we can conclude that it has wheels. Well-known implementations of this type ofrepresentation include ontologies such as Cyc (Lenat, 1995), semantic networks for NLP such as WordNet (Fellbaum,1998), and Google’s Knowledge Graph.

In the NLP community, distributional representations are an increasingly prominent alternative to the classical sym-bolic representations. They require no manual work because they are built automatically by observing large volumesof text (Turney & Pantel, 2010); their underlying idea is the intuition that the meaning of a word is reflected by thestatistical distribution of the contexts where it appears – the distributional hypothesis (Harris, 1954). Practically, arepresentation is realized as a vector: a point in a geometrical space. This can be seen as a compact representation ofthe word’s statistical properties, and is computed either by a statistical analysis of the word’s co-occurrence patterns,or as a by-product of training a neural network (Baroni, Dinu, & Kruszewski, 2014). The most important relation inthis model is similarity: a motorcycle is something quite similar to a scooter. Similarity of meaning is operationalizedin terms of the geometry of the vector space, by defining a distance metric.

These two families of concept representations are obviously very different, and they have different strengths and weak-nesses. The traditional symbolic representations are more detailed and interpretable, but they are extremely costly todevelop and typically suffer from brittleness and low coverage. The distributional representations, on the other hand,tend to have a much better coverage and have the additional advantage that knowledge can be discovered automati-cally, but since the representations build on vectors rather than symbols, they are harder to interpret, and don’t (at themoment) support logical inferences in a reliable way.

In this work, we argue that symbolic structural representations and distributional representations provide complemen-tary information, and that new representations should be developed that combine the strengths of the two approaches.As an instance of this, we present an algorithm (Johansson & Nieto Piña, 2015) that maps symbolic concepts definedin a semantic network into a distributional vector space. We demonstrate its practical utility in two NLP applications:1) word sense disambiguation – given a word such as file in a text, does it refer to a tool or a collection of data on a harddisk? 2) lexicon expansion – given a few examples of the category FOOD, e.g. pizza, sushi, find new words belongingto that category, e.g. labneh, seitan.

References

Baroni, M., Dinu, G., & Kruszewski, G. (2014). Don’t count, predict! A systematic comparison of context-countingvs. context-predicting semantic vectors. In Proceedings of the 52nd Annual Meeting of the Association forComputational Linguistics (Volume 1: Long Papers) (p. 238-247). Baltimore, United States.

Fellbaum, C. (Ed.). (1998). WordNet: An electronic lexical database. MIT Press.Harris, Z. (1954). Distributional structure. Word, 10(23).Johansson, R., & Nieto Piña, L. (2015). Embedding a semantic network in a word space. In Proceedings of the 2015

Conference of the North American Chapter of the Association for Computational Linguistics: Human LanguageTechnologies (p. 1428-1433). Denver, United States.

Lenat, D. B. (1995). CYC: A large-scale investment in knowledge infrastructure. Communications of the ACM, 38(11),33-38.

Turney, P. D., & Pantel, P. (2010). From frequency to meaning: Vector space models of semantics. Journal of ArtificialIntelligence Research, 37, 141-188.

16

Page 19: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Consider Clojure: A modern Lisp that runs on Java and Javascript hosts

Robert Johansson1,2 & Arne Jönsson1

1Department of Computer and Information Science, Linköping University, Sweden

2Department of Clinical Neuroscience, Karolinska Institute, Sweden

[email protected], [email protected]

Developing software is a key methodology in cognitive science. Lisp is a family of programming languages thathistorically has been very influential in cognitive science in general and in the field of artificial intelligence inparticular. Scientists and practitioners alike were drawn to Lisp due to its intelligent design and elegance.However, for various reasons it has become more and more uncommon to use Lisp in cognitive science and AIresearch.

Clojure is a modern Lisp language that compiles both to the Java virtual machine and to Javascript. This enablesus to write fast, stand-alone applications in Lisp that runs on computers, smartphones and in web browsers -everything written in the same language. Clojure encourages functional programming – an approach to softwaredevelopment in where we model our application in terms of data flowing through the system. The design andimplementation of an application then become a process where the developer writes modular parts thattransforms data. Such workflow open up for very elegant solutions to some of today's problems in softwaredevelopment in general and in the field of web applications in particular.

Clojure can be used for everything from resource-intensive server-side applications to lightweight applicationsthat runs in the browser or as a smartphone application. In addition, Clojure has a rich eco-system of freelyavailable libraries to make development become like building things with LEGO.

In this talk, we will give a technical demonstration of the language in where we demonstrate various aspects ofthe language that is relevant for cognitive science researchers and practitioners. We will also demonstrate an e-Health application that has been written in Clojure. It enables clinical practitioners to use the Internet to providepsychological treatment to individuals with for example depression and anxiety. Our experiences with Clojure indeveloping this application will be described. We have also made efforts to teach software development withClojure to clinical psychologists to enable them to write e-Health web applications without any background insoftware development. This project will also be described in the talk.

We believe that Clojure combines the best of both worlds – elegance and performance. With this talk, we hope todemonstrate why we believe Clojure is a perfect fit for both research and practice in the field of cognitivescience.

References

Johansson, R. (in preparation). Functional programming with Clojure.Johansson, R. (in preparation). Writing the code for ICBT web applications.

17

Page 20: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Framing mechanistic processes in bacteria as cognition

Simon Klein 1

1Master's student at the Department of Psychology, Umeå University

[email protected]

Purpose: The presentation wishes to expand human intuitions about cognition, allowing us to view cognition as something that can and does arise through entirely natural means. Background: The constructivist framework of info-computationalism (cf., Dodig-Crnkovic, 2014) will be used as the basis for describing and understanding if and how we should view cognitive processes in bacteria. Info-computationalism describes reality as made up of protoinformation. When agents, in a broad sense of the word, interact with the external world and perform computations on their perception of the protoinformation, information is realized. In this manner, agents construct their own reality based on their interaction with the external world. Since info-computationalism implies that agency and information-processing are ubiquitous phenomena, the question arises how cognition occurs in simpler organisms. Method: The presentation will highlight processes in bacteria that perform functions similar to accepted forms of cognition, but are generally accepted to be entirely “mechanistic”, in the sense of being mechanisms that are fully explainable as natural processes. From this departure point, remarks will be made concerning implications for cognition in general. Example: One of the examples will be the regulation of cytolysin production in the pathogenic Enterococcus faecalis bacteria, as reviewed by Bassler and Losick (2006). The two sub-units of cytolysin are normally bound to each other in a stable complex. However, the larger sub-unit has a higher affinity to the target cells of E. faecalis, leading to the division of the cytolysin complex when target cells are present. The smaller sub-unit can subsequently bind to receptors on the membrane of E. faecalis, inducing an increased production and secretion of cytolysin, leading to a stronger attack on the target cell. If framed as a cognitive process of decision-making, E. faecalis can be seen as actively gathering information concerning its environment in order to adjust its behavior according to external factors (i.e., the presence or absence of a target cell). Conclusion: Examples of mechanistic processes that functionally resemble cognition can be used to expand our view of cognition and may provide clues toward a general theory of cognition.

References

Bassler, B. L. & Losick, R. (2006). Bacterially speaking. Cell, 125, 237-246.Dodig-Crnkovic, G. (2014). Info-computational constructivism and cognition. Constructivistic Foundations,

9(2), 223-231.

18

Page 21: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Sharing of Affective Value in Joint Action Robert Lowe, University of Skövde

Joint Action is a phenomenon that is typically described as a type of social interaction requiring coordination among two or more co-actors in order to achieve a common goal. I describe present work, of myself and colleagues, that concerns how affective valuations can be shared, and then facilitate joint action. I will discuss ongoing experimental work in combination with a neural computational hypothesis for sharing of affective value based on Associative Two-Process (ATP) theory.

ATP entails the use of two memory processes that mitigate response choice (decision making) – a retrospective process concerned with typical stimulus-response learning, and a prospective process whereby outcome expectancies triggered by antecedent stimuli bring to bear on the response choice. The existence of both processes has been evidenced by a number of different experimental set-ups designed to prise apart pavlovian and instrumental components of learning. These experimental set-ups have been used to evaluate the effect of differential outcomes (and expectancies thereof), i.e. when different stimuli and responses are associated with different outcomes such as qualitatively or quantitatively differentiable rewards.

ATP theory has been used to describe animal and human behavioural choice that concerns differential outcome expectancies (Urcuioli 2005, Lowe et al. 2014, 2016). It has been used to explain individual learning and decision-making but until now has not been applied to social interaction. We suggest it can provide a mechanism for allowing affective valued outcomes of others to bring to bear on decision making that concerns one’s own actions in the absence of knowledge of the others’ outcome eliciting actions. Such a mechanism can thereby provide a means for facilitating online coordination without a given agent requiring strong monitoring of the other agent’s activity.

References

Lowe, R. Almér, A. Lindblad, G., Gander, P, Michael, J and Vesper, C. (2016, in press). Minimalist Social-Affective Value for Use in Joint Action: A Neural-Computational Hypothesis, Frontiers in Computational Neuroscience.

Lowe, R., Sandamirskaya, Y., and Billing, E. (2014). “A neural dynamic model of associative two-process theory: the differential outcomes effect and infant development,” in Development and Learning and Epigenetic Robotics (ICDLEpirob) (Genoa), 440–447.

Urcuioli, P. J. (2005). Behavioral and associative effects of differential outcomes in discrimination learning. Anim. Learn. Behav. 33, 1–21. doi: 10.3758/BF0319604.

19

Page 22: 2016 Conference Proceedings

The decision making process at an emergency department

Kajsa Nalin1

1Division of Cognition and Communication, Department of Applied IT, University of Gothenburg

[email protected]

Consider having a stomach pain so intense that you need to seek emergency, you want to know what is wrong and get treated. Once at the emergency department you meet at least one nurse and one physician, and your visit is part of a decision making process aimed to identify a diagnosis and/or a treatment for your stomach problems. In research, this process is more often than not broken down into sub-processes before being studied, researchers thus looking at different parts of the process whether it be from a task perspective, a staff category perspective or a patient perspective.

The study presented here was designed as to catch the whole decision making process, from the patient entering the emergency department until departure. One of the main reasons for doing so was the belief that decision making cannot be lifted out of context, nor is by definition something that happens within the head of an individual but within a system of individuals and artefacts. This view on decision making is heavily influenced by the theory of distributed cognition (Hollan, Hutchins, & Kirsh, 2000; Hutchins, 1995, 2000, 2014). By following 33 patients through the entire visit at the emergency department, recording communication between patients and staff, as well as staff communicating regarding patients – a broad understanding and description of the decision making process from a system view was possible. One of the major findings from the study results concerned artefacts and their interplay with staff in the information propagation. Another finding was related to the role of feedback in the decision making process.

As for the first of these findings, many of the computerised systems had little interconnectivity with each other, making the staff responsible for information propagation between certain artefacts as well as between artefacts and staff, and staff to staff. A recurrent computer problem involved the instability of the computer environment. At every night study occasion, the computers went slow and were at times impossible to use. Normal routines were overthrown and administrational work piled up. Several members of staff also discussed general instability of computer applications. Moreover, one of the applications had limited capacity of information storage, resulting in that staff invented an abbreviation system to make better use of the artefact.

On the role of feedback in decision making, there is no unanimous view (Archer, 2010; Kluger & DeNisi, 1996), however it was obvious from a number of observation opportunities that feedback was desired by several physicians included in the study. At least two physicians communicated that they deliberately delayed signing of patient journals of special interest from a feedback perspective. This way, they were able to enter the journal for a longer period of time following the patient being referred from the ED, thus being able to follow the patient’s journey at the ward.

Future research areas involve how to stabilise and better integrate parts of the decision making system, and to investigate if and how feedback can be improved to physicians.

References

Archer, J. C. (2010). State of the science in health professional education: effective feedback. Medical education, 44(1), 101-108.

Hollan, J., Hutchins, E., & Kirsh, D. (2000). Distributed cognition: toward a new foundation for human-computer interaction research. ACM Transactions on Computer-Human Interaction (TOCHI), 7(2), 174-196.

Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Hutchins, E. (2000). Distributed cognition. International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences. Hutchins, E. (2014). The cultural ecosystem of human cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 27(1), 34-49. Kluger, A. N., & DeNisi, A. (1996). The effects of feedback interventions on performance: a historical review, a

meta-analysis, and a preliminary feedback intervention theory. Psychological Bulletin, 119(2), 254.

20

Page 23: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Concepts and Conceptual Frameworks in Motion

Joel Parthemore

University of Skövde

[email protected]

Concepts are the primary means by which conceptual agents encounter the world and structure their

understanding of it. This paper develops a line of thought through a number of my recent publications: namely,

that concepts and the conceptual frameworks of which they form part cannot simply be open to change, so as to

function effectively as concepts, but are in fact in a state of constant if often incremental motion, requiring close

examination to be seen. This goes against the prevailing wisdom that concepts are defined precisely by their

stability. (Indeed, it is not uncommon to claim, as Jerry Fodor (1998) does, that concepts cannot change, because

the things they track in the mind-independent world are presumed not to change.) Such stability can seem

obligated on concepts, if they are to be systematic and productive in the ways they are generally taken to be, in

keeping with Gareth Evans’ (1982) Generality Constraint.

Although a degree of stability is, indeed, required, it is one that – so this paper argues – belies an underlying

motion that applies even to the seemingly most fixed of concepts: say, mathematical concepts of prime numbers

or “evenness” or “oddness”. Such concepts evolve because the number theory on which they are based evolves,

both for the individual (progressing in her understanding of such matters) and the wider society and the species

itself: a view that can be seen as finding support in the later Bertrand Russell (1923). Making explicit a view

some would find already implicit in Peter Gärdenfors’ (2004) conceptual spaces theory, the idea is that concepts

must be stable enough to apply across unboundedly many contexts but also must adapt at least in small ways to

each new context in which they are applied. Given a world we have reason to view as ultimately based on

fluidity and motion, concepts – if they are to reflect that underlying reality accurately, as they are surely meant to

do – must also be in motion. The appropriate metaphor here is that of a drop of pond water that appears inert

until examined under a microscope, at which point it is seen to be teeming with movement.

Concepts impose a degree of order and stability onto a constantly moving world, setting out boundaries on

underlying continua. That is, the well-known psychological phenomenon of categorical perception (see e.g.

Harnad, 1990) applies not just to perceptual continua but much more broadly. At the same time, concepts are

part of that world. As I argued in (Parthemore, 2011) and elsewhere, it would be a mistake to assume that the

(relatively) stable representations we observe when we reflect upon our concepts as concepts are the same as the

conceptual entities we possess and employ pre-reflectively: as we surely must do, most of the time. The latter,

being somehow closer to the world they reflect, are also more in motion.

Finally, the theoretical and empirical implications of the view, for philosophy of mind, cognitive science, and AI

research, are examined.

References

Evans, G. (1982). Varieties of Reference, J. McDowell (ed.). Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.

Fodor, J. (1998). Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.

Gärdenfors, P. (2004 [2000]). Conceptual Spaces: The Geometry of Thought. Cambridge, Massachusetts, USA:

Bradford Books.

Harnad, S. (1990 [1987]). Category induction and representation. In S. Harnad (ed.), Categorical Perception:

The Groundwork of Cognition (535–565). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

Parthemore, J. (2011). Concepts Enacted: Confronting the Obstacles and Paradoxes Inherent in Pursuing a

Scientific Understanding of the Building Blocks of Human Thought. PhD thesis. Falmer, Brighton, UK:

University of Sussex. http://sro.sussex.ac.uk/6954/ (Accessed 9 September 2016).

Russell, B. (1923). Vagueness. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 1(2): 84-92.�

21

Page 24: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Formalizing Analogies

Ulf Persson1

[email protected]

Our purpose is to present toy examples of self-sufficient entities (think of simpleorganisms as bacteria or even insects) moving around in an environment makingdecisions and ultimately forming plans for survival. The environment could bereal or virtual, but for practical reasons we will confine ourselves to the latter, atleast initially. The point is not to aim for biological realism, although of coursethe latter can serve as an inspiration, but for a simple and flexible system witha potential for extensive development. Ultimately the aim is to lay down thebasis for a general intelligence, although we suspect that this is an ambitionwhose difficulty is underestimated by the AI-community.

In this talk we will concentrate on reasoning and explore a formal model foranalogies, the purpose of which is to transfer knowledge and insight from onedomain to another. We stress that this is a first step and does not capture thetrue scope of analogical reasoning, which so far has evaded any formalization. Inthe simplest case a domain may consist of objects, along with relations, includingunitary ones. An analogy between two domain consists of a map from objectsto objects preserving the relations. In practice this is too rigid a set-up, inthe extreme case we are talking about isomorphisms merely involving a changeof names. Instead analogies are only approximate and their strengths do notfollow from their a priori existencies as from their discoveries, as well as relatingnot directly to objects and relations formally defined in the domains, but toemerging structures. Thus the technical problem is to describe a procedure todiscover analogies, which due to the combinatorial explosion cannot be done bya head-on approach, and to exploit them (maybe to discover further analogies).

ReferencesStrannegard, C., Nizamani, A. R., Juel, J., & Persson, U. (2016). Learning

and reasoning in unknown domains. Journal of Artificial General Intelligence,7(1), 104127.

Strannegard, C., Nizamani, A. R., & Persson, U. (2016). Integrating ax-iomatic and analogical reasoning. In International Conference on Artificial Gen-eral Intelligence

1Department of Mathematics, Chalmers University of Technology

1

22

Page 25: 2016 Conference Proceedings

What am I supposed to do now? Appropriate level of understanding the system – from

highly automated driving perspective.

Veronika Petrovych1, Jan Andersson1 & Tom Ziemke2

1The Swedish National Road and Transport Research Institute(VTI)

2Linköping University

[email protected]

Highly automated driving is expected to soon come to the general driving scene around the world and is

anticipated not only by government officials who see it as a possibility to reduce accident-related deaths on the

roads and influence congestion. Potential users mostly expect automation to take away routinely performed

driving-related tasks and leave time to engage in non-driving tasks.

Advancement in automated systems within passenger cars has boost many topics, ranging from effect on society

to possible infrastructural changes. However, the next change that is actually introduced is the change within the

car – automated systems with different level of control. That is why the first challenge is to understand how

drivers react and interact with the systems that have different purposes and often overlap.

One of the challenges is to ensure that in case of necessity a driver is able to take over from the car and perform

appropriate actions. This can be achieved by including the driver passively even when no urgency is present, i.e.

“keeping in the loop”. However, not only does the driver need to stay informed, but he also needs to know what

actions are expected of him and how to perform them. And given that extreme take over situation will most

probably occur rarely for individual drivers, they might be unprepared to handle it. Habituation with the system

is based on normal, non-critical situations, whereas the action from the driver is most likely to be requested in a

critical condition. This may lead to inappropriate or inadequate response to a take-over request issued by the car

to the driver. Quality of take over requests processing is one measure that can explain level of understanding in

drivers as well as readiness to act in an appropriate manner.

Existing interfaces highly focus on entertainment whereas information about current status of the system

involved or current mode is presented in an obscured way leading to possible misinterpretation of information as

well as inability to react in a timely fashion. While simple, this information may be insufficient for the driver

who is requested to take over control after being “out of the loop” for a period of time. The information the

driver receives prior to in-car system use is highly limited, having drivers often experience a certain function for

the first time when being on the road. Therefore, the task is to ensure appropriate information about the system

given to the driver prior and during the usage.

Investigating highly-automated driving in a driving simulator is common as systems with high level of

automation are not yet fully available in private vehicles. However, a driving simulator environment is a

promising one for manipulating criticality, environmental and system constraints which allows to create a

realistic yet controlled environment for the drivers – potential users of automated systems in private vehicles.

References

Norman, D. A. (1990). The ‘problem’ with automation: Inappropriate feedback and interaction, not ‘over-

automation’. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. B, Biological Sciences, 327, 585–

593

Sarter, N., Woods, D.D., and Billings, C.E. (1997). Automation Surprises. In G. Salvendy (Ed.), Handbook of

Human Factors and Ergonomics (2nd edition) pp. 1926-1943 23

Page 26: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Stanton, N. A., & Young, M. S. (2005). Driver behaviour with adaptive cruise control. Ergonomics, 48, 1294-

1313.

Wickens, C., (2002) Automation types, consequences of imperfect automation, automation and situation

awareness, effects on attention, resources, and task management. Presented at the Humans, Automation and

Issues of Trust Workshop, Adelphi, MD.

24

Page 27: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Learning and Reasoning for Survival

Claes Strannegård1,2

1Department of Applied Information Technology, Chalmers University of Technology2Department of Philosophy, Linguistics and Theory of Science, University of Gothenburg

[email protected]

This talk is about work in progress concerning general intelligence in the context of artificial life (Tuci, Giagkos, Wil-son, & Hallam, 2016). I will discuss an artificial animal (or animat (Wilson, 1986)) designed for general intelligence.My intention is to follow the "animat path to AI" (Wilson, 1991) and thus create a system that is autonomous, versatile,and computationally tractable. Concretely I aim for a system with (1) a set of sensors, (2) a set of motors, (3) a numberof vital needs, (4) a set of special sensor nodes that indicate the status of each of the vital needs, (5) a decision-makingmechanism that aims for survival by keeping all the vital needs satisfied as long as possible, (7) a knowledge base thatmay be empty at the outset and continuously develop over time using online learning, and (8) cognitive resources thatare all strictly bounded in all dimensions. The idea is that (1)-(6) will ensure autonomy; (7) will ensure versatility viageneric mechanisms for knowledge development and reasoning; and (8) will ensure computational tractability.

Ideally a generic system of this kind may develop spider-like features if it develops in a spider’s environment (witha spider’s body) and fish-like features in a fish’s environment. Note that such a system may develop with or withoutinteraction with humans, similarly to a dog that could either be trained by humans via its existing motivational systemor develop in the wild without ever interacting with humans. Consequently, depending on how the system is trained, itmay or may not end up being useful for human problem solving purposes.

I will sketch how a system satisfying (1)-(8) can be constructed by combining our developing system (Strannegård& Nizamani, 2016) with a version of Bach’s motivational system (Bach, 2015). The system continuously receivessensory input from the environment and gradually develops its knowledge base in the form of an annotated graph thatgeneralizes the notion of Markov Decision Process. A key idea is that the operators driving the development of theknowledge base are all motivated from the perspective of survival.

The proposed system supports several types of learning, including online learning, one-shot learning, and versionsof multi-objective reinforcement learning (Vamplew, Dazeley, Berry, Issabekov, & Dekker, 2011). It also supportsdifferent kinds of symbolic and sub-symbolic reasoning, including versions of multi-objective Monte-Carlo tree search(Wang & Sebag, 2012).

References

Bach, J. (2015). Modeling motivation in MicroPsi 2. In 8th International Conference on Artificial General Intelligence,Berlin (pp. 3–13).

Strannegård, C., & Nizamani, A. R. (2016). Integrating symbolic and sub-symbolic reasoning. In 9th InternationalConference on Artificial General Intelligence, New York City (pp. 171–180).

Tuci, E., Giagkos, A., Wilson, M., & Hallam, J. (Eds.). (2016). From animals to animats. 1st International Conferenceon the Simulation of Adaptive Behavior. Springer.

Vamplew, P., Dazeley, R., Berry, A., Issabekov, R., & Dekker, E. (2011). Empirical evaluation methods for multi-objective reinforcement learning algorithms. Machine Learning, 84(1-2), 51–80.

Wang, W., & Sebag, M. (2012). Multi-objective Monte-Carlo tree search. In Asian Conference on Machine Learning(Vol. 25, pp. 507–522).

Wilson, S. W. (1986). Knowledge growth in an artificial animal. In Adaptive and Learning Systems (pp. 255–264).Springer.

Wilson, S. W. (1991). The animat path to AI. In 1st International Conference on the Simulation of Adaptive Behavior.Springer.

25

Page 28: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Finding Patterns Inside and Between Symbolic Domains

Claes Strannegård1,2

1Department of Applied Information Technology, Chalmers University of Technology2Department of Philosophy, Linguistics and Theory of Science, University of Gothenburg

[email protected]

A recent survey of computer programs that solve certain types of IQ test problems indicates that most of these programsare specialized on a single type of problem, e.g. number sequences, progressive matrices, or analogies (Martınez-Plumed, Hernández-Orallo, Schmid, Siebers, & Dowe, 2016). Moreover, these programs typically perform a searchinside a relatively limited set of pre-defined patterns.

In this talk I will sketch an extension of our developing system ALICE IN WONDERLAND (Strannegård, Nizamani,& Persson, 2016; Strannegård, Nizamani, Juel, & Persson, 2016) for learning and reasoning in arbitrary symbolicdomains. After learning, this extended system can solve simple problems that concern, e.g. number sequences, pro-gressive matrices, and analogies. The system starts with an empty knowledge base that it continuously updates inresponse to observations of the external world. To update the knowledge base, it uses memorization, forgetting, gen-eralization, and analogy formation. A general proof system with bounded cognitive resources is used for drawingconclusions from the knowledge base. The system solves problems by attempting to compress symbolic expressionsusing proof rules belonging to the knowledge base. It can learn patterns in arbitrary symbolic sources and it reasons bycombining deduction, induction, abduction, and analogies. Thus the system can be used for finding patterns inside aswell as between symbolic domains.

References

Martınez-Plumed, F., Hernández-Orallo, J., Schmid, U., Siebers, M., & Dowe, D. L. (2016). Historical account ofcomputer models solving IQ test problems. In G. A. Kaminka et al. (Eds.), European Conference on ArtificialIntelligence (Vol. 285).

Strannegård, C., Nizamani, A. R., Juel, J., & Persson, U. (2016). Learning and reasoning in unknown domains. Journalof Artificial General Intelligence, 7(1), 104–127.

Strannegård, C., Nizamani, A. R., & Persson, U. (2016). Integrating axiomatic and analogical reasoning. In Interna-tional Conference on Artificial General Intelligence.

26

Page 29: 2016 Conference Proceedings

Ethical Decisions: Influenced by Time Pressure, Well Described by One-Dimensional Value-of-Life Scale

Leon R. Sütfeld1, Richard Gast1, Peter König1 & Gordon Pipa1

1Faculty of Cognitive Science, University of Osnabrück

[email protected]

With the emergence of self-driving cars, the field of machine ethics is becoming relevant on a large scale and is moving into the public focus. While the expectations with respect to road safety are high (Pelmerini et al., 2014), some accidents are unavoidable, and ethics will often come into play (Goodall, 2014a, Bonnefon et al., 2015). Sophisticated algorithms will define acceptable levels of risk in various situations, and weigh up multiple undesirable but unavoidable outcomes against each other (Goodall, 2014b). Making decisions that are consistent with human values is the benchmark for such algorithms, but the best way to assess and implement these values empirically is still unclear. In the present study, we observed human behavior in ethical dilemma situations, using both immersive virtual reality and text-based representations of the scenarios. Utilizing logistic regression models, we show that human ethical behavior can be well described by a one-dimensional value-of-life scale, and we examine the influence of time pressure on the decision making process.

References

Palmerini, E., Azzarri, F., Battaglia, F., Bertolini, A., Carnevale, A., Carpaneto, J., ... & Koops, B. J. (2014). Guidelines on Regulating Robotics.

Goodall, N.J. (2014a) Machine Ethics and Automated Vehicles. In Road Vehicle Automation (G. Meyer and S. A. Beiker, eds.), Springer, Berlin.

Bonnefon, J. F., Shariff, A., & Rahwan, I. (2015). Autonomous Vehicles Need Experimental Ethics: Are We Ready for Utilitarian Cars?. arXiv preprint arXiv:1510.03346.

Goodall, N. (2014b). Ethical decision making during automated vehicle crashes. Transportation Research Record: Journal of the Transportation Research Board, (2424), 58-65.

27

Page 30: 2016 Conference Proceedings

The relationship between the nature of an artificial agent’s body,its social presence, and its influence on people’s decisions.

Sam Thellman & Tom Ziemke

Department of Computer and Information Science, Linköping University

[email protected], [email protected]

Experimental work comparing robots with virtual agents has shown that robots typically elicit more favorable userresponses than virtual agents in social interaction with people. A recently published meta-analysis by Li (2015), basedon 62 statistically significant differences between robots and virtual agents observed in 33 experimental works, foundthat in 73% of cases robots were found to achieve more positive results. These results include (but are not limited to)robots: being perceived as more socially present (e.g. Fasola & Matri, 2013; Lee et al., 2006); exhibiting greater socialinfluence (e.g. Bainbridge et al., 2009); and being more enjoyable to users overall (e.g. Hasegawa et al., 2010). Hence,the overall outcome of Li’s meta-analysis is that robots in general – or on average – are more effective than virtualagents in social interaction contexts. Furthermore, Li concluded that the benefits of robots are due to their physicalpresence, i.e. their co-location with users, rather than their physical embodiment/bodies.

To further explore the importance of presence to social interaction we conducted a pilot study (N = 60) investigatinghow physical presence relates to social presence and social influence (Thellman, 2016; Thellman et al., 2016). Partic-ipants were randomly assigned to interact with either a physical robot or a simulated version of the same robot (seeFig. 1) during a one-shot variant of the ultimatum game. The robot gave an offer fixed at 20 SEK (apx. $2.3) out of100 SEK and the participant responded by pressing a green (accept) or red (decline) button on an input device. Socialinfluence was measured by registering participant responses to the offer made by the robot; a method based on theassumption that a higher accept rate in one of the experimental conditions indicates a higher degree of social influenceon part of the robot in that condition, relative to the other condition. Social presence – defined by Lee et al. (2004,p. 41) as “the experience of artificial objects as social actors that manifest humanness” – was measured using a scaleadopted from Lee et al. (2006).

Contrary to the tested hypotheses, which were based on Li’s conclusions about the benefits of physical presence, theresults of the experiment showed that neither the extent to which the agent was perceived as socially present nor thesocial influence of the agent was affected by its robotic or virtual embodiment. However, the agent (regardless ofembodiment) exhibited more social influence on participants’ decisions the more socially present it was perceived.This suggests two things: firstly that the social presence of an agent is significant to its success in social interactionwith people; and secondly that physical presence and social presence might be independent from each other, i.e. theextent to which an agent is experienced as socially present might be unaffected of whether it is robotically or virtuallyembodied. Further research is needed to establish whether these two propositions are correct, and to this end futurestudies must incorporate different artificial agents and different methods of measuring social presence and influence.

Figure 1: Physical and simulated (virtual) robot featured in experiment.

28

Page 31: 2016 Conference Proceedings

References

Bainbridge, W.A., Hart, J., Kim, E.S., Scassellati, B. (2010). The benefits of interactions with physically present robotsover video-displayed agents. Int. J. Soc. Robot., 3(1), 41–52.

Fasola, J., Mataric, M. (2013). A socially assistive robot exercise coach for the elderly. Journal of Human-RobotInteraction, 2(2), 3-32.

Hasegawa, D., Cassell, J., Araki, K. (2010). The Role of Embodiment and Perspective in Direction-Giving Systems.In AAAI Fall Symposium: Dialog with Robots.

Lee, K. M. (2004). Presence, Explicated. Communication Theory, 14(1), 27–50.

Lee, K. M., Jung, Y., Kim, J., & Kim, S. R. (2006). Are Physically Embodied Social Agents Better than DisembodiedSocial Agents?: The Effects of Physical Embodiment, Tactile Interaction, and People’s Loneliness in Human-RobotInteraction. Int. J. of Hum-Comp. St., 64(10), 962–973.

Li, J. (2015). The Benefit of Being Physically Present: A Survey of Experimental Works Comparing Copresent robots,Telepresent Robots and Virtual Agents. Int. J. Hum-Comp. St., 77, 23–37.

Thellman, S. (2016). Social Dimensions of Robotic versus Virtual Embodiment, Presence and Influence. (Master’sthesis). Linköpings universitet

Thellman, S., Silvervarg, A., Gulz, A., Ziemke, T. (2016). Physical vs Virtual Embodiment and Effects on Social Pres-ence and Influence. In: Proceedings of the 25th IEEE International Symposium on Robot and Human InteractiveCommunication. New York, USA.

29

Page 32: 2016 Conference Proceedings

30